FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   483   484   485   486   487   488   489   490   491   492   493   494   495   496   497   498   499   500   501   502   503   504   505   506   507  
508   509   510   511   512   513   514   515   516   517   518   519   520   521   522   523   524   525   526   527   528   529   530   531   532   >>   >|  
on, and are obedient to the reason, they are proper to man. And in this way they can be the subject of human virtue. Reply Obj. 2: Just as human flesh has not of itself the good of virtue, but is made the instrument of a virtuous act, inasmuch as being moved by reason, we "yield our members to serve justice"; so also, the irascible and concupiscible powers, of themselves indeed, have not the good of virtue, but rather the infection of the _fomes:_ whereas, inasmuch as they are in conformity with reason, the good of reason is begotten in them. Reply Obj. 3: The body is ruled by the soul, and the irascible and concupiscible powers by the reason, but in different ways. For the body obeys the soul blindly without any contradiction, in those things in which it has a natural aptitude to be moved by the soul: whence the Philosopher says (Polit. i, 3) that the "soul rules the body with a despotic command" as the master rules his slave: wherefore the entire movement of the body is referred to the soul. For this reason virtue is not in the body, but in the soul. But the irascible and concupiscible powers do not obey the reason blindly; on the contrary, they have their own proper movements, by which, at times, they go against reason, whence the Philosopher says (Polit. i, 3) that the "reason rules the irascible and concupiscible powers by a political command" such as that by which free men are ruled, who have in some respects a will of their own. And for this reason also must there be some virtues in the irascible and concupiscible powers, by which these powers are well disposed to act. Reply Obj. 4: In choice there are two things, namely, the intention of the end, and this belongs to the moral virtue; and the preferential choice of that which is unto the end, and this belongs to prudence (Ethic. vi, 2, 5). But that the irascible and concupiscible powers have a right intention of the end in regard to the passions of the soul, is due to the good disposition of these powers. And therefore those moral virtues which are concerned with the passions are in the irascible and concupiscible powers, but prudence is in the reason. ________________________ FIFTH ARTICLE [I-II, Q. 56, Art. 5] Whether the Sensitive Powers of Apprehension Are the Subject of Virtue? Objection 1: It would seem that it is possible for virtue to be in the interior sensitive powers of apprehension. For the sensitive appetite can be the subject of virt
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   483   484   485   486   487   488   489   490   491   492   493   494   495   496   497   498   499   500   501   502   503   504   505   506   507  
508   509   510   511   512   513   514   515   516   517   518   519   520   521   522   523   524   525   526   527   528   529   530   531   532   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

reason

 

powers

 

concupiscible

 

irascible

 

virtue

 

Philosopher

 
blindly
 

things

 
belongs
 

intention


prudence

 
sensitive
 
passions
 
choice
 

command

 
virtues
 

subject

 
proper
 

regard

 

disposition


obedient
 

disposed

 

preferential

 

concerned

 

Objection

 

Virtue

 

Subject

 

appetite

 
apprehension
 

interior


Apprehension

 

ARTICLE

 

Powers

 

Sensitive

 

Whether

 

respects

 

justice

 

contradiction

 
natural
 
aptitude

members
 

begotten

 
infection
 
despotic
 

political

 
conformity
 

movements

 

instrument

 

wherefore

 
entire