FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   492   493   494   495   496   497   498   499   500   501   502   503   504   505   506   507   508   509   510   511   512   513   514   515   516  
517   518   519   520   521   522   523   524   525   526   527   528   529   530   531   532   533   534   535   536   537   538   539   540   541   >>   >|  
ord with his knowledge, but contrary thereto. Wherefore, just as science has always a relation to good, as stated above (A. 2, ad 3), so it is with art: and it is for this reason that it is called a virtue. And yet it falls short of being a perfect virtue, because it does not make its possessor to use it well; for which purpose something further is requisite: although there cannot be a good use without the art. Reply Obj. 2: In order that man may make good use of the art he has, he needs a good will, which is perfected by moral virtue; and for this reason the Philosopher says that there is a virtue of art; namely, a moral virtue, in so far as the good use of art requires a moral virtue. For it is evident that a craftsman is inclined by justice, which rectifies his will, to do his work faithfully. Reply Obj. 3: Even in speculative matters there is something by way of work: e.g. the making of a syllogism or of a fitting speech, or the work of counting or measuring. Hence whatever habits are ordained to such like works of the speculative reason, are, by a kind of comparison, called arts indeed, but "liberal" arts, in order to distinguish them from those arts that are ordained to works done by the body, which arts are, in a fashion, servile, inasmuch as the body is in servile subjection to the soul, and man, as regards his soul, is free (_liber_). On the other hand, those sciences which are not ordained to any such like work, are called sciences simply, and not arts. Nor, if the liberal arts be more excellent, does it follow that the notion of art is more applicable to them. ________________________ FOURTH ARTICLE [I-II, Q. 57, Art. 4] Whether Prudence Is a Distinct Virtue from Art? Objection 1: It would seem that prudence is not a distinct virtue from art. For art is the right reason about certain works. But diversity of works does not make a habit cease to be an art; since there are various arts about works widely different. Since therefore prudence is also right reason about works, it seems that it too should be reckoned a virtue. Obj. 2: Further, prudence has more in common with art than the speculative habits have; for they are both "about contingent matters that may be otherwise than they are" (Ethic. vi, 4, 5). Now some speculative habits are called arts. Much more, therefore, should prudence be called an art. Obj. 3: Further, it belongs to prudence, "to be of good counsel" (Ethic. vi, 5). But counse
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   492   493   494   495   496   497   498   499   500   501   502   503   504   505   506   507   508   509   510   511   512   513   514   515   516  
517   518   519   520   521   522   523   524   525   526   527   528   529   530   531   532   533   534   535   536   537   538   539   540   541   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

virtue

 

reason

 

prudence

 

called

 

speculative

 

ordained

 
habits
 

Further

 
sciences
 

matters


liberal

 
servile
 
applicable
 
ARTICLE
 

notion

 
simply
 

excellent

 
follow
 

FOURTH

 

Whether


reckoned
 

common

 

contingent

 

belongs

 

counsel

 

counse

 

widely

 

Objection

 
Virtue
 

Distinct


distinct

 

diversity

 

Prudence

 

fitting

 

possessor

 

purpose

 

perfect

 

requisite

 
perfected
 
Philosopher

Wherefore
 

science

 
thereto
 
contrary
 

knowledge

 
relation
 

stated

 

comparison

 

counting

 
measuring