FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399   400   401   402   403   404   405   406   407   408   409   410   411   412  
413   414   415   416   417   418   419   420   421   422   423   424   425   426   427   428   429   430   431   432   433   434   435   436   437   >>   >|  
e which are not cows (e.g. buffaloes) have also horns. Thus, it seems that when Pras'astapada says that he is giving us the view of Ka@nada he is faithful to it. Pras'astapada says that wherever there is smoke there is fire, if there is no fire there is no smoke. When one knows this concomitance and unerringly perceives the smoke, he remembers the concomitance and feels certain that there is fire. But with regard to Ka@nada's enumeration of types of inference such as "a cause is inferred from its effect, or an effect from the cause," etc., Pras'astapada holds that these are not the only types of inference, but are only some examples for showing the general nature of inference. Inference merely shows a connection such that from this that can be inferred. He then divides inference into two classes, d@r@s@ta (from the experienced characteristics of one member of a class to another member of the same class), and samanyato d@r@s@ta. D@r@s@ta (perceived resemblance) is that where the previously known case and the inferred case is exactly of the same class. Thus as an example of it we can point out that by perceiving that only a cow has a hanging mass of flesh on its neck (_sasna_), I can whenever I see the same hanging 350 mass of flesh at the neck of an animal infer that it is a cow. But when on the strength of a common quality the inference is extended to a different class of objects, it is called samanyato d@r@s@ta. Thus on perceiving that the work of the peasants is rewarded with a good harvest I may infer that the work of the priests, namely the performance of sacrifices, will also be rewarded with the objects for which they are performed (i.e. the attainment of heaven). When the conclusion, to which one has arrived (_svanis'citartha_) is expressed in five premisses for convincing others who are either in doubt, or in error or are simply ignorant, then the inference is called pararthanumana. We know that the distinction of svarthanumana (inference for oneself) and pararthanumana (inference for others) was made by the Jains and Buddhists. Pras'astapada does not make a sharp distinction of two classes of inference, but he seems to mean that what one infers, it can be conveyed to others by means of five premisses in which case it is called pararthanumana. But this need not be considered as an entirely new innovation of Pras'astapada, for in IX. 2, Ka@nada himself definitely alludes to this distinction (_asyeda@m karyy
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399   400   401   402   403   404   405   406   407   408   409   410   411   412  
413   414   415   416   417   418   419   420   421   422   423   424   425   426   427   428   429   430   431   432   433   434   435   436   437   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

inference

 

astapada

 
inferred
 

pararthanumana

 

distinction

 

called

 
hanging
 
perceiving
 

samanyato

 

member


objects
 
classes
 
rewarded
 

premisses

 

effect

 

concomitance

 
attainment
 

expressed

 

harvest

 

sacrifices


priests

 

performance

 

performed

 

heaven

 

svanis

 

arrived

 

conclusion

 

citartha

 

Buddhists

 

considered


infers

 

conveyed

 

innovation

 

asyeda

 

alludes

 
simply
 
ignorant
 

svarthanumana

 

oneself

 

convincing


enumeration
 
regard
 

Inference

 

nature

 

general

 

examples

 
showing
 

remembers

 
perceives
 

giving