FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   427   428   429   430   431   432   433   434   435   436   437   438   439   440   441   442   443   444   445   446   447   448   449   450   451  
452   453   454   455   456   457   458   459   460   461   462   463   464   465   466   467   468   469   470   471   472   473   474   475   476   >>   >|  
alid to the cognizor at the time that he has the cognition as any real judgment could be. If subsequent experience rejects it, that does not matter, for it is admitted in Mima@msa that when later experience finds out the defects of any perception it can invalidate the original perception which was self-valid at the time of its production [Footnote Ref. 1]. It is easy to see that the Mima@msa had to adopt this view of illusion to maintain the doctrine that all cognition at the moment of its production is valid. The akhyati theory ___________________________________________________________________ [Footnote 1: See _Prakara@napancika, S'astradipika_, and _S'lokavarttika_, sutra 2.] 387 tries to establish the view that the illusion is not due to any positive wrong knowledge, but to a mere negative factor of non-apprehension due to certain weakness of mind. So it is that though illusion is the result, yet the cognition so far as it is cognition, is made up of two elements, the present perception and memory, both of which are true so far as they are individually present to us, and the cognition itself has all the characteristics of any other valid knowledge, for the mark of the validity of a cognition is its power to prompt us to action. In doubtful cognitions also, as in the case "Is this a post or a man?" what is actually perceived is some tall object and thus far it is valid too. But when this perception gives rise to two different kinds of remembrance (of the pillar and the man), doubt comes in. So the element of apprehension involved in doubtful cognitions should be regarded as self-valid as any other cognition. Inference. S'abara says that when a certain fixed or permanent relation has been known to exist between two things, we can have the idea of one thing when the other one is perceived, and this kind of knowledge is called inference. Kumarila on the basis of this tries to show that inference is only possible when we notice that in a large number of cases two things (e.g. smoke and fire) subsist together in a third thing (e.g. kitchen, etc.) in some independent relation, i.e. when their coexistence does not depend upon any other eliminable condition or factor. It is also necessary that the two things (smoke and fire) coexisting in a third thing should be so experienced that all cases of the existence of one thing should also be cases involving the existence of the other, but the cases of the existenc
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   427   428   429   430   431   432   433   434   435   436   437   438   439   440   441   442   443   444   445   446   447   448   449   450   451  
452   453   454   455   456   457   458   459   460   461   462   463   464   465   466   467   468   469   470   471   472   473   474   475   476   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

cognition

 

perception

 
illusion
 

knowledge

 

things

 

relation

 

apprehension

 

factor

 

present

 

inference


production

 
experience
 
doubtful
 

cognitions

 
existence
 

perceived

 

Footnote

 

object

 

Inference

 

remembrance


element

 

pillar

 

involved

 

regarded

 
coexistence
 

independent

 
kitchen
 

depend

 

experienced

 

involving


existenc

 
coexisting
 

eliminable

 

condition

 

subsist

 
number
 

called

 
Kumarila
 

notice

 

permanent


maintain

 

doctrine

 
moment
 

Prakara

 

napancika

 
astradipika
 

theory

 
akhyati
 

original

 

invalidate