FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102  
103   104   105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   122   123   124   125   126   127   >>   >|  
ossible infinity of a series of 'perceptions'. [1] B. 532-3, M. 315. [2] B. 523, M. 309. [3] B. 521, M. 308. This contention, if successful, is clearly important. If it could be shown that the treatment of the world as a thing in itself is the source of a contradiction, we should have what at least would seem a strong, if not conclusive, ground for holding that the world is a phenomenon, and, consequently, that the distinction between phenomena and things in themselves is valid. Professor Cook Wilson has, however, pointed out that Kant's own doctrine does not avoid the difficulty. For, though, according to Kant, the infinity of actual representations of spaces and times is only possible, yet the possibilities of these representations will be themselves infinite, and, as such, will give rise to contradictions similar to those involved in the infinity of space and time. Moreover, as Professor Cook Wilson has also pointed out, there is no contradiction involved in the thought of the world as spatial and temporal; for, as we see when we reflect, we always presuppose that space and time are infinite, and we are only tempted to think that they must be finite, because, when maintaining that the world must be a whole, we are apt to make the false assumption, without in any way questioning it, that any whole must be finite. CHAPTER V TIME AND INNER SENSE The arguments by which Kant seeks to show that time is not a determination of things in themselves but only a form of perception are, _mutatis mutandis_, identical with those used in his treatment of space.[1] They are, therefore, open to the same criticisms, and need no separate consideration. [1] Cf. B. 46-9, Secs. 4, 5 and 6 (a), M. 28-30, Secs. 5, 6 and 7 (a) with B. 38-42, Sec. 2 (1-4), and Sec. (3) to (a) inclusive, M. 23-6, Secs. 2, 3, and 4 (a). The only qualification needed is that, since the parts of time cannot, like those of space, be said to exist simultaneously, B. Sec. 4 (5), M. Sec. 5, 5 is compelled to appeal to a different consideration from that adduced in the parallel passage on space (B. Sec. 2 (4), M. Sec. 2, 4). Since, however, B. Sec. 4 (5), M. Sec. 5, 5 introduces no new matter, but only appeals to the consideration already urged (B. Sec. 4, 4, M. Sec. 5, 4), this difference can be neglected. B. Sec. 5, M. Sec. 6 adds a remark about change which does not affect the
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102  
103   104   105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   122   123   124   125   126   127   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

infinity

 

consideration

 

things

 

pointed

 

Wilson

 

finite

 
infinite
 

involved

 

representations

 
Professor

treatment

 

contradiction

 

mutandis

 

mutatis

 
perception
 

matter

 
appeals
 

difference

 

identical

 

determination


change
 

CHAPTER

 

affect

 

arguments

 

neglected

 
remark
 

introduces

 

simultaneously

 

compelled

 

appeal


inclusive

 

qualification

 

questioning

 

separate

 

criticisms

 
needed
 

adduced

 
parallel
 

passage

 

strong


conclusive

 
ground
 

phenomena

 

distinction

 

holding

 

phenomenon

 
source
 

ossible

 
series
 
perceptions