FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   103   104   105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   122   123   124   125   126   127  
128   129   130   131   132   133   134   135   136   137   138   139   140   141   142   143   144   145   146   147   148   149   150   151   152   >>   >|  
ravenes the second implication of perception to which attention has been drawn. Again, in the second place, if we go on to ask how Kant is misled into doing this, we see that it is because he contravenes the first implication of perception. In virtue of his theory of perception[10] he interposes a _tertium quid_ between the reality perceived and the percipient, in the shape of an 'appearance'. This _tertium quid_ gives him something which can plausibly be regarded as at once a perception and something perceived. For, though from the point of view of the thing in itself an appearance is an appearance or a perception of it, yet, regarded from the point of view of what it is in itself, an appearance is a reality perceived of the kind called mental. Hence space and time, being characteristics of an appearance, can be regarded as at once characteristics of our perception of a reality, viz. of a thing in itself, and characteristics of a reality perceived, viz. an appearance. Moreover, there is another point of view from which the treatment of bodies in space as appearances or phenomena gives plausibility to the view that space, though a form of perception, is a characteristic of a reality. When Kant speaks of space as the form of phenomena the fact to which he refers is that all bodies are spatial.[11] He means, not that space is a way in which we perceive something, but that it is a characteristic of things perceived, which he _calls_ phenomena, and which _are_ bodies. But, since in his statement of this fact he substitutes for bodies phenomena, which to him are perceptions, his statement can be put in the form 'space is _the form of perceptions_'; and the statement in this form is verbally almost identical with the statement that space is _a form of perception_. Consequently, the latter statement, which _should_ mean that space is a way in which we perceive things, is easily identified with a statement of which the meaning is that space is a characteristic of something perceived.[12] [9] Cf. p. 51, note 1. [10] Cf. p. 30 and ff. [11] Cf. p. 39. [12] It can be shown in the same way, _mutatis mutandis_ (cp. p. 111), that the view that time, though the form of inner perception, is a characteristic of a reality gains plausibility from Kant's implicit treatment of our states as appearances due to ourselves. Again, Kant's account of time will be found to treat something represented or
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   103   104   105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   122   123   124   125   126   127  
128   129   130   131   132   133   134   135   136   137   138   139   140   141   142   143   144   145   146   147   148   149   150   151   152   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

perception

 

reality

 
perceived
 

statement

 

appearance

 
bodies
 

phenomena

 
characteristic
 
regarded

characteristics

 
appearances
 

perceive

 

things

 

treatment

 

perceptions

 

plausibility

 

tertium

 

implication


easily

 
identified
 
meaning
 

Consequently

 

substitutes

 
verbally
 
identical
 

states

 

implicit


attention
 

account

 

represented

 
mutandis
 

mutatis

 

mental

 
theory
 

virtue

 

Moreover


called

 

percipient

 

ravenes

 
interposes
 

contravenes

 
plausibly
 

spatial

 
speaks
 
refers

misled