FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   447   448   449   450   451   452   453   454   455   456   457   458   459   460   461   462   463   464   465   466   467   468   469   470   471  
472   473   474   475   476   477   478   479   480   481   482   483   484   485   486   487   488   489   490   491   492   493   494   495   496   >>   >|  
not a special virtue; for nothing prevents a certain genus from containing a species which is operative in every other species of that same genus, even as the sun has an influence over all bodies. Reply Obj. 3: Things done are indeed the matter of prudence, in so far as they are the object of reason, that is, considered as true: but they are the matter of the moral virtues, in so far as they are the object of the appetitive power, that is, considered as good. _______________________ SIXTH ARTICLE [II-II, Q. 47, Art. 6] Whether Prudence Appoints the End to Moral Virtues? Objection 1: It would seem that prudence appoints the end to moral virtues. Since prudence is in the reason, while moral virtue is in the appetite, it seems that prudence stands in relation to moral virtue, as reason to the appetite. Now reason appoints the end to the appetitive power. Therefore prudence appoints the end to the moral virtues. Obj. 2: Further, man surpasses irrational beings by his reason, but he has other things in common with them. Accordingly the other parts of man are in relation to his reason, what man is in relation to irrational creatures. Now man is the end of irrational creatures, according to _Polit._ i, 3. Therefore all the other parts of man are directed to reason as to their end. But prudence is "right reason applied to action," as stated above (A. 2). Therefore all actions are directed to prudence as their end. Therefore prudence appoints the end to all moral virtues. Obj. 3: Further, it belongs to the virtue, art, or power that is concerned about the end, to command the virtues or arts that are concerned about the means. Now prudence disposes of the other moral virtues, and commands them. Therefore it appoints their end to them. _On the contrary,_ The Philosopher says (Ethic. vi, 12) that "moral virtue ensures the rectitude of the intention of the end, while prudence ensures the rectitude of the means." Therefore it does not belong to prudence to appoint the end to moral virtues, but only to regulate the means. _I answer that,_ The end of moral virtues is human good. Now the good of the human soul is to be in accord with reason, as Dionysius declares (Div. Nom. iv). Wherefore the ends of moral virtue must of necessity pre-exist in the reason. Now, just as, in the speculative reason, there are certain things naturally known, about which is _understanding,_ and certain things of which we obtain knowledge
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   447   448   449   450   451   452   453   454   455   456   457   458   459   460   461   462   463   464   465   466   467   468   469   470   471  
472   473   474   475   476   477   478   479   480   481   482   483   484   485   486   487   488   489   490   491   492   493   494   495   496   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

prudence

 

reason

 

virtues

 

Therefore

 

virtue

 

appoints

 
relation
 
irrational
 

things

 

species


appetitive

 
ensures
 

Further

 

rectitude

 
concerned
 

matter

 

appetite

 
creatures
 

directed

 

considered


object

 

actions

 

Philosopher

 
disposes
 

command

 
commands
 

contrary

 

belongs

 

necessity

 

Wherefore


speculative

 

obtain

 

knowledge

 

understanding

 

naturally

 

belong

 

appoint

 

intention

 

regulate

 

Dionysius


declares
 

accord

 

answer

 

ARTICLE

 

prevents

 

Appoints

 

Prudence

 

Whether

 

operative

 

influence