FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73   74   75  
76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   >>   >|  
etrical judgements can in no way be 'explained'. It is not in the least explained or made easier to accept by the supposition that objects are 'phenomena'. These judgements must be accepted as being what we presuppose them to be in making them, viz. the direct apprehension of necessities of relation between real characteristics of real things. To explain them by reference to the phenomenal character of what is known is really--though contrary to Kant's intention--to throw doubt upon their validity; otherwise, they would not need explanation. As a matter of fact, it is _impossible_ to question their validity. In the act of judging, doubt is impossible. Doubt can arise only when we subsequently reflect and temporarily lose our hold upon the consciousness of necessity in judging.[54] The doubt, however, since it is non-existent in our geometrical consciousness, is really groundless,[55] and, therefore, the problem to which it gives rise is unreal. Moreover if, _per impossibile_, doubt could be raised, it could not be set at rest. No vindication of a judgement in which we are conscious of a necessity could do more than take the problem a stage further back, by basing it upon some other consciousness of a necessity; and since this latter judgement could be questioned for precisely the same reason, we should only be embarking upon an infinite process. [54] Cf. Descartes, _Princ. Phil._ i. Sec. 13, and _Medit._ v sub fin. [55] The view that kinds of space other than that with which we are acquainted are possible, though usually held and discussed by mathematicians, belongs to them _qua_ metaphysicians, and not _qua_ mathematicians. We may now consider Kant's conclusion in abstraction from the arguments by which he reaches it. It raises three main difficulties. In the first place, it is not the conclusion to be expected from Kant's own standpoint. The phenomenal character of space is inferred, not from the fact that we make judgements at all, but from the fact that we make judgements of a particular kind, viz. _a priori_ judgements. From this point of view empirical judgements present no difficulty. It should, therefore, be expected that the qualities which we attribute to things in empirical judgements are not phenomenal, but belong to things as they are. Kant himself implies this in drawing his conclusion concerning the nature of space. "Space does not represent any quality of things in thems
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73   74   75  
76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

judgements

 

things

 

necessity

 
phenomenal
 

consciousness

 

conclusion

 

validity

 

expected

 

mathematicians

 
impossible

problem

 

judging

 

explained

 
empirical
 

judgement

 

character

 

infinite

 

metaphysicians

 

Descartes

 

process


belongs

 

embarking

 
acquainted
 

discussed

 

attribute

 

belong

 

implies

 
qualities
 

difficulty

 
present

drawing
 

quality

 
represent
 

nature

 
priori
 

reaches

 

raises

 

arguments

 

abstraction

 

inferred


standpoint

 

difficulties

 

reason

 

unreal

 

reference

 

contrary

 

explain

 

relation

 
characteristics
 

intention