FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   49   50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73  
74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   >>   >|  
ether, and to do this is implicitly to question the validity of our thought about the nature of our own mind, as well as the validity of our thought about things independent of the mind. Yet Kant's argument, in the form in which it has just been stated, presupposes that our thought is valid at any rate when it is concerned with our perceptions of things, even if it is not valid when concerned with the things as they are in themselves. [48] Cf. p. 17. [49] For the reasons which led Kant to draw this distinction between empirical and _a priori_ judgements, cf. pp. 21-2. This consideration leads to the second criticism. The supposition that space is only a form of perception, even if it be true, _in no way assists_ the explanation of the universal validity of geometrical judgements. Kant's argument really confuses a _necessity_ of relation with the _consciousness of a necessity_ of relation. No doubt, if it be a law of our perceiving nature that, whenever we perceive an object as a three-sided figure, the object as perceived contains three angles, it follows that any object as perceived will conform to this law; just as if it be a law of things as they are in themselves that three-sided figures contain three angles, all three-sided figures will in themselves have three angles. But what has to be explained is the universal applicability, not of a law, but of a judgement about a law. For Kant's real problem is to explain why _our judgement_ that a three-sided figure must contain three angles must apply to all three-sided figures. Of course, if it be granted that in the judgement we apprehend the true law, the problem may be regarded as solved. But how are we to know that what we judge _is_ the true law? The answer is in no way facilitated by the supposition that the judgement relates to our perceiving nature. It can just as well be urged that what we think to be a necessity of our perceiving nature is not a necessity of it, as that what we think to be a necessity of things as they are in themselves is not a necessity of them. The best, or rather the only possible, answer is simply that that of which we apprehend the necessity must be true, or, in other words, that we _must_ accept the validity of thought. Hence nothing is gained by the supposition that space is a form of sensibility. If what we judge to be necessary is, as such, valid, a judgement relating to things in themselves will be as valid as a judge
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   49   50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73  
74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

necessity

 

things

 

judgement

 
thought
 

validity

 

nature

 

angles

 

perceiving

 

object

 
supposition

figures

 

judgements

 

universal

 
apprehend
 

relation

 

answer

 

problem

 

perceived

 

figure

 

argument


concerned

 

applicability

 
explain
 

explained

 

accept

 

simply

 

gained

 
relating
 

sensibility

 
regarded

solved
 

granted

 
relates
 

facilitated

 
explanation
 

reasons

 

empirical

 

distinction

 

perceptions

 

independent


implicitly

 

presupposes

 

stated

 

priori

 

consciousness

 

confuses

 

geometrical

 

perceive

 
question
 

assists