FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   836   837   838   839   840   841   842   843   844   845   846   847   848   849   850   851   852   853   854   855   856   857   858   859   860  
861   862   863   864   865   866   867   868   869   870   871   872   873   874   875   876   877   878   879   880   881   882   883   884   885   >>   >|  
atise on Morals in the second part of this work (I-II, Q. 85, seqq.; Q. 109). _______________________ THIRD ARTICLE [I, Q. 83, Art. 3] Whether Free-will Is an Appetitive Power? Objection 1: It would seem that free-will is not an appetitive, but a cognitive power. For Damascene (De Fide Orth. ii, 27) says that "free-will straightway accompanies the rational nature." But reason is a cognitive power. Therefore free-will is a cognitive power. Obj. 2: Further, free-will is so called as though it were a free judgment. But to judge is an act of a cognitive power. Therefore free-will is a cognitive power. Obj. 3: Further, the principal function of free-will is to choose. But choice seems to belong to knowledge, because it implies a certain comparison of one thing to another, which belongs to the cognitive power. Therefore free-will is a cognitive power. _On the contrary,_ The Philosopher says (Ethic. iii, 3) that choice is "the desire of those things which are in us." But desire is an act of the appetitive power: therefore choice is also. But free-will is that by which we choose. Therefore free-will is an appetitive power. _I answer that,_ The proper act of free-will is choice: for we say that we have a free-will because we can take one thing while refusing another; and this is to choose. Therefore we must consider the nature of free-will, by considering the nature of choice. Now two things concur in choice: one on the part of the cognitive power, the other on the part of the appetitive power. On the part of the cognitive power, counsel is required, by which we judge one thing to be preferred to another: and on the part of the appetitive power, it is required that the appetite should accept the judgment of counsel. Therefore Aristotle (Ethic. vi, 2) leaves it in doubt whether choice belongs principally to the appetitive or the cognitive power: since he says that choice is either "an appetitive intellect or an intellectual appetite." But (Ethic. iii, 3) he inclines to its being an intellectual appetite when he describes choice as "a desire proceeding from counsel." And the reason of this is because the proper object of choice is the means to the end: and this, as such, is in the nature of that good which is called useful: wherefore since good, as such, is the object of the appetite, it follows that choice is principally an act of the appetitive power. And thus free-will is an appetitive power. Reply Obj. 1: Th
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   836   837   838   839   840   841   842   843   844   845   846   847   848   849   850   851   852   853   854   855   856   857   858   859   860  
861   862   863   864   865   866   867   868   869   870   871   872   873   874   875   876   877   878   879   880   881   882   883   884   885   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

choice

 

cognitive

 
appetitive
 

Therefore

 

appetite

 

nature

 

counsel

 
choose
 

desire


called

 

required

 

judgment

 

Further

 

reason

 
belongs
 

things

 

object

 

intellectual


proper

 

principally

 

refusing

 

concur

 
Aristotle
 
proceeding
 
describes
 

wherefore

 
accept

preferred

 
leaves
 
intellect
 
inclines
 

knowledge

 
Objection
 
Appetitive
 

Damascene

 

Whether


Morals
 
ARTICLE
 

comparison

 
contrary
 

implies

 

Philosopher

 

belong

 

straightway

 

accompanies


rational

 
function
 

principal

 
answer