FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   185   186   187   188   189   190   191   192   193   194   195   196   197   198   199   200   201   202   203   204   205   206   207   208   209  
210   211   212   213   214   215   216   217   218   219   220   221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   229   230   231   232   233   234   >>   >|  
judgement have in some way to be rendered more concrete in respect of time. The account of the schematism, therefore, is an attempt to get out of the false position reached by appealing to Formal Logic for the list of categories. Nevertheless, the mention of a sensuous condition under which alone the categories can be employed[3] should have suggested to Kant that the transcendental deduction was defective, and, in fact, in the second version of the transcendental deduction two paragraphs[4] are inserted which take account of this sensuous condition. [2] The cause of Kant's procedure is, of course, to be found in the unreal way in which he isolates conception from judgement. [3] B. 175, M. 106. [4] B. Secs. 24 and 26, M. Secs. 20 and 22. The beginning of Kant's account of schematism may be summarized thus: 'Whenever we subsume an individual object of a certain kind, e. g. a plate, under a conception, e. g. a circle, the object and the conception must be homogeneous, that is to say, the individual must possess the characteristic which constitutes the conception, or, in other words, must be an instance of it. Pure conceptions, however, and empirical perceptions, i. e. objects of empirical perception, are quite heterogeneous. We do not, for instance, perceive cases of cause and effect. Hence the problem arises, 'How is it possible to subsume objects of empirical perception under pure conceptions?' The possibility of this subsumption presupposes a _tertium quid_, which is homogeneous both with the object of empirical perception and with the conception, and so makes the subsumption mediately possible. This _tertium quid_ must be, on the one side, intellectual and, on the other side, sensuous. It is to be found in a 'transcendental determination of time', i. e. a conception involving time and involved in experience. For in the first place this is on the one side intellectual and on the other sensuous, and in the second place it is so far homogeneous with the category which constitutes its unity that it is universal and rests on an _a priori_ rule, and so far homogeneous with the phenomenon that all phenomena are in time[5]. Such transcendental determinations of time are the schemata of the pure conceptions of the understanding.' Kant continues as follows: [5] It may be noted that the argument here really fails. For though phenomena as involving temporal relations, might possibly be
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   185   186   187   188   189   190   191   192   193   194   195   196   197   198   199   200   201   202   203   204   205   206   207   208   209  
210   211   212   213   214   215   216   217   218   219   220   221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   229   230   231   232   233   234   >>   >|  



Top keywords:
conception
 

empirical

 

sensuous

 
transcendental
 
homogeneous
 
conceptions
 

object

 

perception

 

account

 

phenomena


subsume
 
subsumption
 

tertium

 

instance

 

objects

 

intellectual

 

constitutes

 

involving

 

individual

 

judgement


condition
 

schematism

 

deduction

 
categories
 

determination

 
respect
 
attempt
 

Formal

 

concrete

 

arises


experience

 

involved

 
appealing
 
presupposes
 

reached

 
possibility
 

mediately

 

position

 

category

 

argument


understanding

 

continues

 
possibly
 

relations

 
temporal
 
schemata
 

determinations

 

universal

 
problem
 

rendered