FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   219   220   221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   229   230   231   232   233   234   235   236   237   238   239   240   241   242   243  
244   245   246   247   248   249   >>  
ct, which is palpably contrary to fact. Again, his aim is to show that we become aware of a succession by presupposing the law of causality. This law, however, is quite general, and only asserts that _something_ must precede an event upon which it follows always and necessarily. Hence by itself it palpably gives no means of determining whether this something is A rather than anything else.[43] Therefore if he were to maintain that the antecedent member of an apprehended objective succession must be thought of as its cause, the analogy would obviously provide no means of determining the antecedent member, and therefore the succession itself, for the succession must be the sequence of B upon some definite antecedent. On the other hand, the view that the cause of B need not be A only incurs the same difficulty in a rather less obvious form. For, even on this view, the argument implies that in order to apprehend two individual perceptions A B as an objective succession, we must know that A _must_ precede B, and the presupposition that B implies a cause in the state of affairs preceding B in no way enables us to say either that A coexists with the cause, or that it is identical with it, and therefore that it must precede B. [43] Cf. B. 165, M. 101, where Kant points out that the determination of particular laws of nature requires experience. Nevertheless, it cannot be regarded as certain that Kant did not think of A, the apprehended antecedent of B, as necessarily the cause of B, for his language is both ambiguous and inconsistent. When he considers the apprehension of a succession from the side of the successive perceptions, he at least tends to think of A B as cause and effect;[44] and it may well be that in discussing the problem from the side of the law of causality, he means the cause of B to be A, although the generality of the law compels him to refer to it as _something_ upon which B follows according to a rule. [44] He definitely implies this, B. 234, M. 142. Further, it should be noticed that to allow as Kant, in effect, does elsewhere[45], that experience is needed to determine the cause of B is really to concede that the apprehension of objective successions is _prior to_, and _presupposed by_, any process which appeals to the principle of causality; for if the principle of causality does not by itself enable us to determine the cause of B, it cannot do more than enable us to pick out th
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   219   220   221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   229   230   231   232   233   234   235   236   237   238   239   240   241   242   243  
244   245   246   247   248   249   >>  



Top keywords:
succession
 

causality

 

antecedent

 
implies
 
objective
 
precede
 

apprehended

 

member

 

perceptions

 

apprehension


enable
 
principle
 

effect

 

palpably

 

necessarily

 

determine

 

experience

 

determining

 

successive

 

points


language
 

requires

 

Nevertheless

 
regarded
 

nature

 
considers
 
inconsistent
 

ambiguous

 

determination

 

concede


successions

 

needed

 
presupposed
 
process
 

appeals

 
noticed
 

generality

 

compels

 

problem

 

discussing


Further

 

Therefore

 
maintain
 

thought

 
sequence
 
provide
 

analogy

 

contrary

 
presupposing
 

asserts