FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   860   861   862   863   864   865   866   867   868   869   870   871   872   873   874   875   876   877   878   879   880   881   882   883   884  
885   886   887   888   889   890   891   892   893   894   895   896   897   898   899   900   901   902   903   904   905   906   907   908   909   >>   >|  
e, as to their demonstrations." ________________________ THIRD ARTICLE [I-II, Q. 95, Art. 3] Whether Isidore's Description of the Quality of Positive Law Is Appropriate? Objection 1: It would seem that Isidore's description of the quality of positive law is not appropriate, when he says (Etym. v, 21): "Law shall be virtuous, just, possible to nature, according to the custom of the country, suitable to place and time, necessary, useful; clearly expressed, lest by its obscurity it lead to misunderstanding; framed for no private benefit, but for the common good." Because he had previously expressed the quality of law in three conditions, saying that "law is anything founded on reason, provided that it foster religion, be helpful to discipline, and further the common weal." Therefore it was needless to add any further conditions to these. Obj. 2: Further, Justice is included in honesty, as Tully says (De Offic. vii). Therefore after saying "honest" it was superfluous to add "just." Obj. 3: Further, written law is condivided with custom, according to Isidore (Etym. ii, 10). Therefore it should not be stated in the definition of law that it is "according to the custom of the country." Obj. 4: Further, a thing may be necessary in two ways. It may be necessary simply, because it cannot be otherwise: and that which is necessary in this way, is not subject to human judgment, wherefore human law is not concerned with necessity of this kind. Again a thing may be necessary for an end: and this necessity is the same as usefulness. Therefore it is superfluous to say both "necessary" and "useful." _On the contrary,_ stands the authority of Isidore. _I answer that,_ Whenever a thing is for an end, its form must be determined proportionately to that end; as the form of a saw is such as to be suitable for cutting (Phys. ii, text. 88). Again, everything that is ruled and measured must have a form proportionate to its rule and measure. Now both these conditions are verified of human law: since it is both something ordained to an end; and is a rule or measure ruled or measured by a higher measure. And this higher measure is twofold, viz. the Divine law and the natural law, as explained above (A. 2; Q. 93, A. 3). Now the end of human law is to be useful to man, as the Jurist states [*Pandect. Justin. lib. xxv, ff., tit. iii; De Leg. et Senat.]. Wherefore Isidore in determining the nature of law, lays down, at first, three
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   860   861   862   863   864   865   866   867   868   869   870   871   872   873   874   875   876   877   878   879   880   881   882   883   884  
885   886   887   888   889   890   891   892   893   894   895   896   897   898   899   900   901   902   903   904   905   906   907   908   909   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

Isidore

 

Therefore

 
measure
 

custom

 

conditions

 

Further

 

measured

 
common
 

higher

 

necessity


superfluous

 

country

 

nature

 

suitable

 
expressed
 

quality

 

wherefore

 

judgment

 

answer

 

Whenever


determining

 

determined

 
cutting
 
Wherefore
 
proportionately
 

concerned

 
usefulness
 

ARTICLE

 
demonstrations
 
stands

authority
 

contrary

 
twofold
 
Justin
 

ordained

 

Divine

 
natural
 
states
 

Pandect

 
explained

Jurist

 

proportionate

 

subject

 

verified

 

stated

 

Quality

 
private
 

framed

 
misunderstanding
 

obscurity