FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   306   307   308   309   310   311   312   313   314   315   316   317   318   319   320   321   322   323   324   325   326   327   328   329   330  
331   332   333   334   335   336   337   338   339   340   341   342   343   344   345   346   347   348   349   350   351   352   353   354   355   >>   >|  
question of fact," says he, "_which is not in the province of moral philosophy to decide_. It very likely may be so. So far as I know, the facts are not sufficiently known to warrant a full opinion on the subject. We will, therefore, suppose it to be the case, and ask, What is the duty of masters _under these circumstances_?" In the discussion of this question, the author comes to the conclusion that a master may hold his slaves in bondage, provided his intentions be good, and with a view to set them at liberty as soon as they shall be qualified for such a state. Moral philosophy, then, it seems, when it closes its eyes upon facts, pronounces that slavery should be _immediately_ abolished; but if it consider facts, which, instead of being denied, are admitted to be "very likely" true, it decides against its immediate abolition! Or, rather, moral philosophy looks at the fact that slavery is an _injury_, in order to see that it should be forthwith abolished; but closes its eyes upon the fact that its abolition may be a still greater injury, lest this foregone conclusion should be called in question! Has moral philosophy, then, an eye only for the facts which lie one side of the question it proposes to decide? Slavery is an _injury_, says Dr. Wayland, and therefore it should be _immediately_ abolished. But its abolition would be a still greater injury, replies the objector. This may be true, says Dr. Wayland: it is highly probable; but then this question of injury is one of fact, which it is not in the province of moral philosophy to decide! So much for the consistency and even-handed justice of the author. The position assumed by him, that questions of fact are not within the province of moral philosophy, is one of so great importance that it deserves a separate and distinct notice. Though seldom openly avowed, yet is it so often tacitly assumed in the arguments and declamations of abolitionists, that it shall be more fully considered in the following section. Sec. V. _The fifth fallacy of the abolitionist._ "Suppose that A has a right to use the body of B according to his--that is, A's--will. Now if this be true, it is true universally; and hence, A has the control over the body of B, and B has control over the body of C, C of D, &c., and Z again over the body of A: that is, every separate will has the right of control over some other body besides its own, and has no right of control over its own body or inte
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   306   307   308   309   310   311   312   313   314   315   316   317   318   319   320   321   322   323   324   325   326   327   328   329   330  
331   332   333   334   335   336   337   338   339   340   341   342   343   344   345   346   347   348   349   350   351   352   353   354   355   >>   >|  



Top keywords:
philosophy
 

question

 

injury

 

control

 

abolition

 

decide

 

province

 

abolished

 
assumed
 

immediately


slavery

 

closes

 

separate

 

conclusion

 
author
 

Wayland

 

greater

 

notice

 

Though

 

highly


replies

 

probable

 
objector
 

deserves

 

handed

 
justice
 

position

 

questions

 

consistency

 
importance

distinct

 
fallacy
 
universally
 

Suppose

 
abolitionist
 

arguments

 

declamations

 
abolitionists
 

tacitly

 

openly


avowed

 
section
 

considered

 

seldom

 

admitted

 

discussion

 
circumstances
 
masters
 
master
 

intentions