FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   179   180   181   182   183   184   185   186   187   188   189   190   191   192   193   194   195   196   197   198   199   200   201   202   203  
204   205   206   207   208   209   210   211   212   213   214   215   216   217   218   219   220   221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   >>   >|  
and certitude are doubtless very fine ideals to play with, but where on this moonlit and dream-visited planet are they found?" Now, among those things regarding which it appears impossible to attain to intellectual certitude, there are matters of great practical moment, and which affect deeply the conduct of life; for example, the doctrines of religion. Here a merely skeptical attitude seems intolerable. In such cases, argues Professor James, "we have the right to believe at our own risk any hypothesis that is live enough to tempt our will." It is important to notice that there is no question here of a logical right. We are concerned with matters regarding which, according to Professor James, we cannot look for intellectual evidence. It is assumed that we believe simply because we choose to believe--we believe arbitrarily. It is further important to notice that what is a "live" hypothesis to one man need not tempt the will of another man at all. As our author points out, a Turk would naturally will to believe one thing and a Christian would will to believe another. Each would will to believe what struck him as a satisfactory thing to believe. What shall we say to this doctrine? I think we must say that it is clearly not a philosophical _method of attaining to truth_. Hence, it has not properly a place in this chapter among the attempts which have been made to attain to the truth of things. It is, in fact, not concerned with truths, but with assumptions, and with assumptions which are supposed to be made on the basis of no evidence. It is concerned with "seemings." The distinction is a very important one. Our Turk cannot, by willing to believe it, make his hypothesis true; but he can make it _seem_ true. Why should he wish to make it seem true whether it is true or not? Why should he strive to attain to a feeling of subjective certainty, not by logically resolving his doubts, but by ignoring them? The answer is given us by our author. He who lives in the midst of doubts, and refuses to cut his knot with the sword of belief, misses the good of life. This is a practical problem, and one of no small moment. In the last section of this book I have tried to indicate what it is wise for a man to do when he is confronted by doubts which he cannot resolve. Into the general question whether even a false belief may not, under some circumstances, be more serviceable than no belief at all, I shall no
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   179   180   181   182   183   184   185   186   187   188   189   190   191   192   193   194   195   196   197   198   199   200   201   202   203  
204   205   206   207   208   209   210   211   212   213   214   215   216   217   218   219   220   221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

belief

 
important
 

concerned

 
hypothesis
 
doubts
 

attain

 

author

 

assumptions

 
certitude
 
evidence

question
 

Professor

 

notice

 

practical

 

moment

 

matters

 

things

 

intellectual

 
distinction
 
subjective

feeling

 

seemings

 

supposed

 

truths

 

strive

 

confronted

 
resolve
 
section
 

general

 
circumstances

serviceable

 
answer
 

logically

 
resolving
 
ignoring
 

problem

 
misses
 

refuses

 

certainty

 
skeptical

religion

 

doctrines

 

conduct

 

attitude

 

argues

 

intolerable

 
deeply
 

affect

 

moonlit

 

ideals