FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   208   209   210   211   212   213   214   215   216   217   218   219   220   221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   229   230   231   232  
233   234   235   236   237   238   239   240   241   242   243   244   245   246   247   248   249   250   251   252   253   254   255   256   257   >>   >|  
lane's trans. of Ibn Khallik[=a]n's _Biographical Dictionary_ (Paris and London, 1842), vol. iii. pp. 130 ff., and Ibn 'Usaibi'a's biography translated in P. de Gayangos' edition of the _History of the Mohammedan Dynasties in Spain_, by al-Maqqari (London, 1840), vol. ii., appendix, p. xii. List of extant works in C. Brockelmann's _Geschichte der arabischen Litteratur_, vol. i. p. 460. For his philosophy cf. T. J. de Boer's _The History of Philosophy in Isl[=a]m_ (London, 1903), ch. vi. (G. W. T.) AVENARIUS, RICHARD HEINRICH LUDWIG (1843-1896), German philosopher, was born in Paris on the 19th of November 1843. His education, begun in Zuerich and Berlin, was completed at the university of Leipzig, where he graduated in 1876. In 1877 he became professor of philosophy in Zuerich, where he died on the 18th of August 1896. At Leipzig he was one of the founders of the _Akademisch-philosophische Verein_, and was the first editor of the _Vierteljahrsschrift fuer wissenschaftliche Philosophie_. In 1868 he published an essay on the Pantheism of Spinoza. His chief works are _Philosophie als Denken der Welt gemaess dem Princip des kleinsten Kraftmasses_ (1876) and the _Kritik der reinen Erfahrung_ (1888-1890). In these works he made an attempt to co-ordinate thought and action. Like Mach, he started from the principle of economy of thinking, and in the _Kritik_ endeavoured to explain pure experience in relation to knowledge and environment. He discovers that statements dependent upon environment constitute pure experience. This philosophy, called Empirio-criticism, is not, however, a realistic but an idealistic dualism, nor can it be called materialism. See Wundt, _Philos. Stud._ xiii. (1897); Carstanjen and Willy in _Zeitsch. f. wiss. Philos_. xx. (1896), 361 ff.; xx. 57 ff.; xxii. 53 ff.; J. Petzoldt's _Einfuehrung in d. Philos. d. reinen Erfahrung_ (1900). AVENGER OF BLOOD, the person, usually the nearest kinsman of the murdered man, whose duty it was to avenge his death by killing the murderer. In primitive societies, before the evolution of settled government, or the uprise of a systematized criminal law, crimes of violence were regarded as injuries of a personal character to be punished by the sufferer or his kinsfolk. This right of vengeance was common to most countries, and in many was the subject of strict regulations and limitations. It was prevented from running into excesses by the law of sanctuary (_q.v._) and i
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   208   209   210   211   212   213   214   215   216   217   218   219   220   221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   229   230   231   232  
233   234   235   236   237   238   239   240   241   242   243   244   245   246   247   248   249   250   251   252   253   254   255   256   257   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

philosophy

 

Philos

 

London

 

reinen

 
Kritik
 

Erfahrung

 

environment

 

experience

 
Zuerich
 

called


Leipzig
 
Philosophie
 

History

 

regulations

 

dualism

 

realistic

 

idealistic

 

strict

 

limitations

 

Carstanjen


Zeitsch
 

materialism

 

subject

 

criticism

 

knowledge

 

sanctuary

 
excesses
 
relation
 

thinking

 
endeavoured

explain

 

discovers

 
prevented
 

Empirio

 

constitute

 
statements
 
running
 

dependent

 

killing

 

murderer


primitive

 

societies

 

avenge

 
kinsman
 

murdered

 
evolution
 

uprise

 

violence

 

systematized

 
criminal