FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   383   384   385   386   387   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399   400   401   402   403   404   405   406   407  
408   409   410   411   412   413   414   415   416   417   418   419   420   421   422   423   424   425   426   427   428   429   430   431   432   >>   >|  
es thus from the event itself; since God made the universe, it was not possible to do better. Such management, far from being contrary to goodness, has rather been prompted by supreme goodness itself. This objection with its solution might have been inferred from what was said with regard to the first objection; but it seemed advisable to touch upon it separately. OBJECTION VIII Whoever cannot fail to choose the best is not free. God cannot fail to choose the best. Therefore God is not free. ANSWER I deny the major of this argument. Rather is it true freedom, and the most perfect, to be able to make the best use of one's free will, and always to exercise this power, without being turned aside either by outward force or by inward passions, whereof the one enslaves our bodies and the other our souls. There is nothing less servile and more befitting the highest degree of freedom than to be always led towards the good, and always by one's own inclination, without any constraint and without any displeasure. And to object that God therefore had need of external things is only a sophism. He creates them freely: but when he had set before him an end, that of exercising his goodness, his wisdom determined him to choose the means most appropriate for obtaining this end. To call that a _need_ is to take the term in a sense not usual, which clears it of all imperfection, somewhat as one does when speaking of the wrath of God. Seneca says somewhere, that God commanded only once, but that he obeys[387] always, because he obeys the laws that he willed to ordain for himself: _semel jussit, semper paret_. But he had better have said, that God always commands and that he is always obeyed: for in willing he always follows the tendency of his own nature, and all other things always follow his will. And as this will is always the same one cannot say that he obeys that will only which he formerly had. Nevertheless, although his will is always indefectible and always tends towards the best, the evil or the lesser good which he rejects will still be possible in itself. Otherwise the necessity of good would be geometrical (so to speak) or metaphysical, and altogether absolute; the contingency of things would be destroyed, and there would be no choice. But necessity of this kind, which does not destroy the possibility of the contrary, has the name by analogy only: it becomes effective not through the mere essence of things, but thr
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   383   384   385   386   387   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399   400   401   402   403   404   405   406   407  
408   409   410   411   412   413   414   415   416   417   418   419   420   421   422   423   424   425   426   427   428   429   430   431   432   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

things

 

choose

 
goodness
 

necessity

 

freedom

 
contrary
 
objection
 
semper
 

jussit

 

commanded


ordain
 

willed

 

clears

 
imperfection
 
commands
 
Seneca
 
speaking
 

universe

 

destroyed

 
choice

contingency

 

absolute

 

metaphysical

 

altogether

 

destroy

 
essence
 

effective

 

possibility

 

analogy

 

geometrical


Nevertheless

 

follow

 
nature
 

obtaining

 

tendency

 

indefectible

 

Otherwise

 
rejects
 

lesser

 

obeyed


turned

 

exercise

 

regard

 

outward

 

enslaves

 
bodies
 
whereof
 

passions

 

inferred

 

OBJECTION