FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   143   144   145   146   147   148   149   150   151   152   153   154   155   156   157   158   159   160   161   162   163   164   165   166   167  
168   169   170   171   172   173   174   175   176   177   178   179   180   181   182   183   184   185   186   187   188   189   190   191   192   >>   >|  
use of them in the formal disputations of graduands in the Universities. It was the custom for the Disputant to expound his argument in this form:-- If so and so is the case, such and such follows. So and so is the case. [.'.] Such and such follows. To which the Respondent would reply: _Accipio antecedentem, nego consequentiam_, and argue accordingly. Petrus Hispanus does not give the Hypothetical Syllogism as a Syllogism: he merely explains the true law of Reason and Consequent in connexion with the Fallacia Consequentis in the section on Fallacies. (_Summulae. Tractatus Sextus._) II.--DISJUNCTIVE SYLLOGISMS. A Disjunctive Syllogism is a syllogism in which the Major Premiss is a DISJUNCTIVE PROPOSITION, _i.e._, one in which two propositions are declared to be mutually incompatible. It is of the form Either A is B, or C is D.[3] If the disjunction between the alternatives is really complete, the form implies four hypothetical propositions:-- (1) If A is B, C is not D. (2) If A is not B, C is D. (3) If C is D, A is not B. (4) If C is not D, A is B. Suppose then that an antagonist has granted you a Disjunctive Proposition, you can, using this as a Major Premiss, extract from him four different Conclusions, if you can get him also to admit the requisite Minors. The Mode of two of these is technically called MODUS PONENDO TOLLENS, the mode that denies the one alternative by granting the other--A is B, _therefore_ C is not D; C is D, _therefore_ A is not B. The other Mode is also twice open, the MODUS TOLLENDO PONENS--A is not B, _therefore_ C is D; C is not D, _therefore_ A is B. Fallacy is sometimes committed through the Disjunctive form owing to the fact that in common speech there is a tendency to use it in place of a mere hypothetical, when there are not really two incompatible alternatives. Thus it may be said "Either the witness is perjured, or the prisoner is guilty," when the meaning merely is that if the witness is not perjured the prisoner is guilty. But really there is not a valid disjunction and a correct use of the disjunctive form, unless four hypotheticals are implied, that is, unless the concession of either involves the denial of the other, and the denial of either the concession of the other. Now the prisoner may be guilty and yet the witness be perjured; so that two of the four hypotheticals, namely-- If the witness is perjured, the prisoner is not gui
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   143   144   145   146   147   148   149   150   151   152   153   154   155   156   157   158   159   160   161   162   163   164   165   166   167  
168   169   170   171   172   173   174   175   176   177   178   179   180   181   182   183   184   185   186   187   188   189   190   191   192   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

prisoner

 

witness

 

perjured

 
Disjunctive
 
guilty
 

Syllogism

 
incompatible
 

Either

 

DISJUNCTIVE

 

propositions


disjunction
 

alternatives

 

hypothetical

 

Premiss

 

hypotheticals

 
concession
 

denial

 

implied

 

TOLLENS

 
correct

denies

 
disjunctive
 

PONENDO

 

alternative

 

technically

 

requisite

 

involves

 
Minors
 

called

 

argument


committed

 

common

 

tendency

 

expound

 

speech

 

Disputant

 

Conclusions

 

meaning

 

custom

 

PONENS


Fallacy

 

TOLLENDO

 

granting

 

Consequent

 

connexion

 

Reason

 
explains
 

Fallacia

 

Summulae

 

Tractatus