FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   189   190   191   192   193   194   195   196   197   198   199   200   201   202   203   204   205   206   207   208   209   210   211   212   213  
214   215   216   217   218   219   220   221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   229   230   231   232   233   234   235   236   237   238   >>   >|  
mea_, iii. 124] [Footnote 2: The truth is, that we see much less than is commonly supposed. Not every impression is attended to that is made on the retina, and unless we do attend we cannot, properly speaking, be said to see. Walking across to college one day, I was startled by seeing on the face of a clock in my way that it was ten minutes to twelve, whereas I generally passed that spot about twenty minutes to twelve. I hurried on, fearing to be late, and on my arrival found myself in very good time. On my way back, passing the clock again, I looked up to see how much it was fast. It marked ten minutes to eight. It had stopped at that time. When I passed before I had really seen only the minute hand. The whole dial must have been on my retina, but I had looked at or attended to only what I was in doubt about, taking the hour for granted. I am bound to add that my business friends hint that it is only absorbed students that are capable of such mistakes, and that alert men of business are more circumspect. That can only be because they are more alive to the danger of error.] CHAPTER III. ASCERTAINMENT OF FACTS OF CAUSATION. I.--_POST HOC ERGO PROPTER HOC_. One of the chief contributions of the Old Logic to Inductive Method was a name for a whole important class of misobservations. The fallacy entitled _Post Hoc ergo Propter Hoc_--"After, therefore, Because of"--consisted in alleging mere sequence as a proof of consequence or causal sequence. The sophist appeals to experience, to observed facts: the sequence which he alleges has been observed. But the appeal is fallacious: the observation on which he relies amounts only to this, that the one event has followed upon the other. This much must be observable in all cases of causal sequence, but it is not enough for proof. _Post hoc ergo propter hoc_ may be taken as a generic name for imperfect proof of causation from observed facts of succession. The standard example of the fallacy is the old Kentish peasant's argument that Tenterden Steeple was the cause of Goodwin Sands. Sir Thomas More (as Latimer tells the story in one of his Sermons to ridicule incautious inference) had been sent down into Kent as a commissioner to inquire into the cause of the silting up of Sandwich Haven. Among those who came to his court was the oldest inhabitant, and thinking that he from his great age must
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   189   190   191   192   193   194   195   196   197   198   199   200   201   202   203   204   205   206   207   208   209   210   211   212   213  
214   215   216   217   218   219   220   221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   229   230   231   232   233   234   235   236   237   238   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

sequence

 

minutes

 

observed

 
passed
 
twelve
 

business

 
fallacy
 

looked

 

retina

 

causal


attended
 

consequence

 

misobservations

 

important

 

consisted

 
alleging
 

Because

 

sophist

 

appeal

 
alleges

experience

 
Propter
 

appeals

 

fallacious

 

relies

 

amounts

 

observation

 
entitled
 

standard

 

commissioner


inquire

 

inference

 

incautious

 

Sermons

 

ridicule

 

silting

 

Sandwich

 

inhabitant

 

oldest

 

thinking


Latimer

 

generic

 

imperfect

 

causation

 

succession

 

propter

 
Goodwin
 

Thomas

 

Steeple

 

Tenterden