FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   239   240   241   242   243   244   245   246   247   248   249   250   251   252   253   254   255   256   257   258   259   260   261   262   263  
264   265   266   267   268   269   270   271   272   273   274   275   276   277   278   279   280   281   282   283   284   285   286   287   288   >>   >|  
not to say a universal group, operates to limit the objectivity. In the aesthetic and moral attitudes we incorporate value in the object decisively. We do not like to think that beauty can be changed with shifting fashions or to affirm that the firmament was ever anything but sublime. It seems to belong to the very essence of right that it is something to which the self can commit itself in absolute loyalty and finality. And, as for good, we may say with Moore in judgments of intrinsic value, at least, "we judge concerning a particular state of things that it would be worth while--would be a good thing--that that state of things should exist, even if nothing else were to exist besides." With regard to this problem of objectivity it is significant in the first place that the kind of situation out of which this object value is affirmed in aesthetic and moral judgments is a social situation. It contrasts in this respect with the economic situation. The economic is indeed social in so far as it sets exchange values, but the object valued is not a social object. The aesthetic and moral object is such an object. Not only is there no contradiction in giving to the symbolic form or the moral act intrinsic value: there is entire plausibility in doing so. For in so far as the situation is really personal, _either member is fundamentally equal to the other and may be treated as embodying all the value of the situation_. The value which rises to consciousness in the situation is made more complete by eliminating from consideration the originating factors, the plural agents of admiration or approval, and incorporating the whole product abstractly in the object. In thus calling attention to the social or personal character of the aesthetic or moral object it is not intended to minimize that factor in the judgment which we properly speak of as the universalizing activity of thought, much less to overlook the importance of the judgmental process itself. The intention is to point out some of the reasons why in one case the thinking process does universalize while in the other it does not, why in one case the judgment is completely objective while in the other it is not. In both aesthetic and moral judgments social art, social action, social judgments, through collective decisions prepare the way for the general non-personal, objective form. It is probable that man would not say, "This is right," using the word as an adjective, if he
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   239   240   241   242   243   244   245   246   247   248   249   250   251   252   253   254   255   256   257   258   259   260   261   262   263  
264   265   266   267   268   269   270   271   272   273   274   275   276   277   278   279   280   281   282   283   284   285   286   287   288   >>   >|  



Top keywords:
object
 

social

 

situation

 

aesthetic

 

judgments

 

personal

 

process

 

judgment

 

economic

 
things

intrinsic

 

objectivity

 

objective

 

factors

 

originating

 

approval

 

prepare

 
consideration
 
probable
 
agents

general

 

plural

 

admiration

 

complete

 

adjective

 

treated

 

embodying

 

fundamentally

 
member
 

incorporating


consciousness
 
eliminating
 

completely

 
universalize
 
overlook
 
activity
 

thought

 

thinking

 
reasons
 
intention

importance
 

judgmental

 

universalizing

 
attention
 
character
 

intended

 

calling

 

decisions

 

product

 

abstractly