FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   214   215   216   217   218   219   220   221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   229   230   231   232   233   234   235   236   237   238  
239   240   241   242   243   244   245   246   247   248   249   250   251   252   253   254   255   256   257   258   259   260   261   262   263   >>   >|  
ry unlawful wish is a sin," which "corroborates or supports" the preceding: and, lastly, "therefore every unlawful wish deserves death," which is the "conclusion or proof." We learn, also, that "sometimes the first is called the premises (_sic_), and sometimes the first premiss"; as also that "the first is sometimes called the proposition, or subject, or affirmative, and the next the predicate, and sometimes the middle term." To which is added, with a mark of exclamation at the end, "but in analyzing the syllogism, there is a middle term, and a predicate too, in each of the lines!" It is clear that Aristotle never enslaved this mind. I have said that logic has no paradoxers, but I was speaking of old time. This science has slept until our own day: Hamilton[707] says there has been "no progress made in {332} the _general_ development of the syllogism since the time of Aristotle; and in regard to the few _partial_ improvements, the professed historians seem altogether ignorant." But in our time, the paradoxer, the opponent of common opinion, has appeared in this field. I do not refer to Prof. Boole,[708] who is not a _paradoxer_, but a _discoverer_: his system could neither oppose nor support common opinion, for its grounds were not in the conception of any one. I speak especially of two others, who fought like cat and dog: one was dogmatical, the other categorical. The first was Hamilton himself--Sir William Hamilton of Edinburgh, the metaphysician, not Sir William _Rowan_ Hamilton[709] of Dublin, the mathematician, a combination of peculiar genius with unprecedented learning, erudite in all he could want except mathematics, for which he had no turn, and in which he had not even a schoolboy's knowledge, thanks to the Oxford of his younger day. The other was the author of this work, so fully described in Hamilton's writings that there is no occasion to describe him here. I shall try to say a few words in common language about the paradoxers. Hamilton's great paradox was the _quantification of the predicate_; a fearful phrase, easily explained. We all know that when we say "Men are animals," a form wholly unquantified in phrase, we speak of _all_ men, but not of all animals: it is _some or all_, some may be all for aught the proposition says. This some-may-be-all-for-aught-we-say, or _not-none,_ is the logician's _some_. One would suppose {333} that "all men are some animals," would have been the logical phrase in all tim
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   214   215   216   217   218   219   220   221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   229   230   231   232   233   234   235   236   237   238  
239   240   241   242   243   244   245   246   247   248   249   250   251   252   253   254   255   256   257   258   259   260   261   262   263   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

Hamilton

 

predicate

 
phrase
 

animals

 
common
 

syllogism

 

Aristotle

 
paradoxer
 

paradoxers

 

opinion


called

 

proposition

 

William

 
middle
 

unlawful

 

mathematics

 
dogmatical
 

learning

 

mathematician

 

combination


Dublin
 

metaphysician

 
schoolboy
 
Edinburgh
 

peculiar

 
erudite
 

unprecedented

 

genius

 

categorical

 

explained


quantification

 

fearful

 

easily

 
wholly
 

unquantified

 

logical

 

suppose

 

logician

 

paradox

 

author


Oxford

 

younger

 
writings
 

occasion

 

language

 

describe

 

knowledge

 

analyzing

 

exclamation

 
speaking