FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   383   384   385   386   387   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399   400   401   402   403   404   405   406   407  
408   409   410   411   412   413   414   415   416   417   418   419   420   421   422   423   424   425   426   427   428   429   430   431   432   >>   >|  
s are still retained. The bases are immovable. Autonomy, absolute oughtness, the formal character of the law of reason, and the incomparable worth of the pure, disinterested disposition--these are the corner stones of the Kantian, nay, of all morals. %3. Theory of the Beautiful and of Ends in Nature.% We now know the laws which the understanding imposes upon nature and those which reason imposes upon the will. If there is a field in which to be (_Sein_) and ought to be (_Sollen_), nature and freedom, which we have thus far been forced to consider antithetical, are reconciled--and that there is such a field is already deducible from the doctrine of the religious postulates (as practical truths or assumptions concerning what is, in behalf of what ought to be), and from the hints concerning a progress in history (in which both powers co-operate toward a common goal)--then the source of its laws is evidently to be sought in that faculty which mediates alike between understanding and reason and between knowing and feeling: in _Judgment_, as the higher faculty of feeling. Judgment, in the general sense, is the faculty of thinking a particular as contained in a universal, and exercises a twofold function: as "determinant" judgment it subsumes the particular under a given universal (a law), as "reflective" it seeks the universal for a given particular. Since the former coincides with the understanding, we are here concerned only with the reflective judgment, judgment in the narrower sense, which does not cognize objects, but judges them, and this according to the principle of purposiveness.[1] [Footnote 1: The universal laws springing from the understanding, to which every nature must conform to become an object of experience for us, determine nothing concerning the particular form of the given reality; we cannot deduce the special laws of nature from them. Nevertheless the nature of our cognitive faculty does not allow us to accept the empirical manifoldness of our world as contingent, but impels us to regard it as purposive or adapted to our knowledge, and to look upon these special laws as if an intelligence had given them in order to make a system of experience possible.] This, in turn, is of two kinds. An object is really or _objectively_ purposive (perfect) when it corresponds to its nature or its determination, formally or _subjectively_ purposive (beautiful) when it is conformed to the nature of our cognitive fa
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   383   384   385   386   387   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399   400   401   402   403   404   405   406   407  
408   409   410   411   412   413   414   415   416   417   418   419   420   421   422   423   424   425   426   427   428   429   430   431   432   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

nature

 

understanding

 

universal

 

faculty

 

reason

 

purposive

 

judgment

 

experience

 

cognitive

 
special

object

 

imposes

 

feeling

 

Judgment

 
reflective
 

coincides

 

conform

 

principle

 

judges

 

narrower


objects

 

cognize

 
concerned
 
Footnote
 

purposiveness

 

springing

 

Nevertheless

 

system

 

objectively

 

beautiful


conformed

 
subjectively
 

formally

 

perfect

 

corresponds

 

determination

 

intelligence

 
accept
 

deduce

 

reality


empirical

 
manifoldness
 
knowledge
 

adapted

 
regard
 

contingent

 

impels

 
determine
 

contained

 

Sollen