FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   44   45   46   47   48   49   50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68  
69   70   71   72   73   74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   >>   >|  
; of the sovereignty of the ruler (_rex major populo; plenitudo potestatis_), and of popular sovereignty[3] (_populus major principe_); of the original and inalienable prerogatives of the generality, and the innate and indestructible right of the individual to freedom; the thought that the sovereign power is superior to positive law _(princeps legibus solutus_), but subordinate to natural law; even tendencies toward the division of powers (legislative and executive), and the representative system. These are germs which, at the fall of Scholasticism and the ecclesiastical reformation, gain light and air for free development. [Footnote 1: Gierke, _Johannes Althusius und die Entwickelung der naturrechtlichen Staatstheorien_, Breslau, 1880; the same, _Deutsches Genossenschaftsrecht_, vol. iii. Sec. II, Berlin, 1881. Cf. further, Sigm. Riezler, _Die literarischen Widersacher der Paepste_, Leipsic, 1874; A. Franck, _Reformateurs et Publicistes de L'Europe_, Paris, 1864.] [Footnote 2: Nicolas' political ideas are discussed by T. Stumpf, Cologne, 1865.] [Footnote 3: Cf. F. von Bezold, _Die Lehre von der Volkssouveraenitaet im Mittelalter_, (Sybel's _Historische Zeitschrift_, vol. xxxvi., 1876).] The modern theory of natural law, of which Grotius was the most influential representative, began with Bodin and Althusius. The former conceives the contract by which the state is founded as an act of unconditional submission on the part of the community to the ruler, the latter conceives it merely as the issue of a (revocable) commission: in the view of the one, the sovereignty of the people is entirely alienated, "transferred," in that of the other, administrative authority alone is granted, "conceded," while the sovereign prerogatives remain with the people. Bodin is the founder of the theory of absolutism, to which Grotius and the school of Pufendorf adhere, though in a more moderate form, and which Hobbes develops to the last extreme. Althusius, on the other hand, by his systematic development of the doctrine of social contract and the inalienable sovereignty of the people, became the forerunner of Locke[1] and Rousseau. [Footnote 1: Ulrich Huber (1674) may be called the first representative of constitutionalism, and so the intermediate link between Althusius and Locke. Cf. Gierke, _Althusius_, p. 290.] The first independent political philosopher of the modern period was Nicolo Machiavelli of Florence (1469-1527). Patrio
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   44   45   46   47   48   49   50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68  
69   70   71   72   73   74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

Althusius

 

Footnote

 

sovereignty

 

representative

 

people

 

conceives

 

political

 

contract

 

natural

 

development


Gierke
 

theory

 

modern

 
inalienable
 

Grotius

 

prerogatives

 

sovereign

 

administrative

 
revocable
 

commission


alienated

 

transferred

 
founded
 

influential

 

Zeitschrift

 
authority
 

community

 

unconditional

 

submission

 

school


constitutionalism
 

called

 
intermediate
 
Rousseau
 

Ulrich

 

Florence

 

Patrio

 

Machiavelli

 

Nicolo

 

independent


philosopher
 

period

 

forerunner

 

Historische

 
Pufendorf
 

adhere

 

absolutism

 

founder

 

granted

 
conceded