FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   48   49   50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72  
73   74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   >>   >|  
mentioned, Heft vii. of his _Untersuchungen zur deutschen Staats- und Rechtsgeschichte_, Breslau, 1880) to the Westphalian, Johannes Althusius (Althusen or Althaus) as a legal philosopher worthy of notice. He was born, 1557, in the Grafschaft Witgenstein; was a teacher of law in Herborn and Siegen from 1586, and Syndic in Emden from 1604 to his death in 1638. His chief legal work was the _Dicaeologica_, 1617 (a recasting of a treatise on Roman law which appeared in 1586), and his chief political work the _Politica_, 1603 (altered and enlarged 1610, and reprinted, in addition, three times before his death and thrice subsequently). Down to the beginning of the eighteenth century he was esteemed or opposed as chief among the _Monarchomachi_, so called by the Scotchman, Barclay (_De Regno et Regali Potestate_, 1600); since that time he has fallen into undeserved oblivion. The sovereign power (_majestas_) of the people is untransferable and indivisible, the authority vested in the chosen wielder of the administrative power is revocable, and the king is merely the chief functionary; individuals are subjects, it is true, but the community retains its sovereignty and has its rights represented over against the chief magistrate by a college of ephors. If the prince violates the compact, the ephors are authorized and bound to depose the tyrant, and to banish or execute him. There is but one normal state-form; monarchy and polyarchy are mere differences in administrative forms. Mention should finally be made of his valuation of the social groups which mediate between the individual and the state: the body politic is based on the narrower associations of the family, the corporation, the commune, and the province. While with Bodin the historical, and with Gentilis the _a priori_ method of treatment predominates, Hugo Grotius[1] combines both standpoints. He bases his system on the traditional distinction of two kinds of law. The origin of positive law is historical, by voluntary enactment; natural law is rooted in the nature of man, is eternal, unchangeable, and everywhere the same. He begins by distinguishing with Gentilis the _jus humanum_ from the _jus divinum_ given in the Scriptures. The former determines, on the one hand, the legal relations of individuals, and, on the other, those of whole nations; it is _jus personale_ and _jus gentium_.[2] [Footnote 1: Hugo de Groot lived 1583-1645. He was born in Delft, became Fiscal of H
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   48   49   50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72  
73   74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

administrative

 

historical

 

Gentilis

 

ephors

 

individuals

 

corporation

 
commune
 

province

 

family

 
associations

individual

 

politic

 

narrower

 

deutschen

 
predominates
 

Grotius

 
treatment
 

method

 

Untersuchungen

 

priori


mediate
 

normal

 

Staats

 

monarchy

 

tyrant

 
banish
 

execute

 

polyarchy

 

valuation

 

social


groups

 

finally

 

differences

 

Mention

 

combines

 
standpoints
 

nations

 
personale
 

relations

 

Scriptures


determines

 
gentium
 

Fiscal

 

Footnote

 

divinum

 

humanum

 
origin
 

positive

 
voluntary
 
distinction