FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   37   38   39   40   41   42   43   44   45   46   47   48   49   50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   >>  
the world, just as is the case in ungeneralized propositions.) It is a mark of a composite symbol that it has something in common with other symbols. 5.5262 The truth or falsity of every proposition does make some alteration in the general construction of the world. And the range that the totality of elementary propositions leaves open for its construction is exactly the same as that which is delimited by entirely general propositions. (If an elementary proposition is true, that means, at any rate, one more true elementary proposition.) 5.53 Identity of object I express by identity of sign, and not by using a sign for identity. Difference of objects I express by difference of signs. 5.5301 It is self-evident that identity is not a relation between objects. This becomes very clear if one considers, for example, the proposition '(x) : fx. z. x = a'. What this proposition says is simply that only a satisfies the function f, and not that only things that have a certain relation to a satisfy the function, Of course, it might then be said that only a did have this relation to a; but in order to express that, we should need the identity-sign itself. 5.5302 Russell's definition of '=' is inadequate, because according to it we cannot say that two objects have all their properties in common. (Even if this proposition is never correct, it still has sense.) 5.5303 Roughly speaking, to say of two things that they are identical is nonsense, and to say of one thing that it is identical with itself is to say nothing at all. 5.531 Thus I do not write 'f(a, b). a = b', but 'f(a, a)' (or 'f(b, b)); and not 'f(a,b). Pa = b', but 'f(a, b)'. 5.532 And analogously I do not write '(dx, y). f(x, y). x = y', but '(dx) . f(x, x)'; and not '(dx, y). f(x, y). Px = y', but '(dx, y). f(x, y)'. 5.5321 Thus, for example, instead of '(x): fx z x = a' we write '(dx). fx . z: (dx, y). fx. fy'. And the proposition, 'Only one x satisfies f( )', will read '(dx). fx: P(dx, y). fx. fy'. 5.533 The identity-sign, therefore, is not an essential constituent of conceptual notation. 5.534 And now we see that in a correct conceptual notation pseudo-propositions like 'a = a', 'a = b. b = c. z a = c', '(x). x = x', '(dx). x = a', etc. cannot even be written down. 5.535 This also disposes of all the problems that were connected with such pseudo-propositions. All the problems that Russell's 'axiom of infinity' brings with it can
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   37   38   39   40   41   42   43   44   45   46   47   48   49   50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   >>  



Top keywords:

proposition

 
propositions
 

identity

 

relation

 

elementary

 

express

 
objects
 

satisfies

 

identical

 
function

things

 
general
 

common

 

problems

 
Russell
 
conceptual
 
pseudo
 

notation

 

construction

 
correct

properties

 

speaking

 

Roughly

 

nonsense

 

written

 

disposes

 

infinity

 
brings
 

connected

 

analogously


constituent
 
essential
 
simply
 

leaves

 

totality

 
delimited
 
alteration
 

composite

 

symbol

 

ungeneralized


symbols

 
falsity
 

Identity

 

satisfy

 

inadequate

 

definition

 

difference

 
Difference
 

object

 
evident