FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   164   165   166   167   168   169   170   171   172   173   174   175   176   177   178   179   180   181   182   183   184   185   186   187   188  
189   190   191   192   193   194   195   196   197   198   199   200   201   202   203   204   205   206   207   208   209   210   211   212   213   >>   >|  
urrence of A, an antecedent, and _p_, a consequent, with concomitant facts or events--and let us represent them thus: Antecedents: A B C A D E Consequents: _p q r_ _p s t_; and suppose further that, in this case, the immediate succession of events can be observed. Then A is probably the cause, or an indispensable condition, of _p_. For, as far as our instances go, A is the invariable antecedent of _p_; and _p_ is the invariable consequent of A. But the two instances of A or _p_ agree in no other circumstance. Therefore A is (or completes) the unconditional antecedent of _p_. For B and C are not indispensable conditions of _p_, being absent in the second instance (Rule II. (b)); nor are D and E, being absent in the first instance. Moreover, _q_ and _r_ are not effects of A, being absent in the second instance (Rule II. (d)); nor are _s_ and _t_, being absent in the first instance. It should be observed that the cogency of the proof depends entirely upon its tending to show the unconditionality of the sequence A-_p_, or the indispensability of A as a condition of _p_. That _p_ follows A, even immediately, is nothing by itself: if a man sits down to study and, on the instant, a hand-organ begins under his window, he must not infer malice in the musician: thousands of things follow one another every moment without traceable connection; and this we call 'accidental.' Even invariable sequence is not enough to prove direct causation; for, in our experience does not night invariable follow day? The proof requires that the instances be such as to show not merely what events _are_ in invariable sequence, but also what _are not_. From among the occasional antecedents of _p_ (or consequents of A) we have to eliminate the accidental ones. And this is done by finding or making 'negative instances' in respect of each of them. Thus the instance A D E _p s t_ is a negative instance of B and C considered as supposable causes of _p_ (and of _q_ and _r_ as supposable effects of A); for it shows that they are absent when _p_ (or A) is present. To insist upon the cogency of 'negative instances' was Bacon's great contribution to Inductive Logic. If we neglect them, and merely collect examples of the sequence A-_p_, this is 'simple enumeration'; and although simple enumeration, when the instances of agreement are numerous enough, may give rise to a strong belief in the connection of phenome
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   164   165   166   167   168   169   170   171   172   173   174   175   176   177   178   179   180   181   182   183   184   185   186   187   188  
189   190   191   192   193   194   195   196   197   198   199   200   201   202   203   204   205   206   207   208   209   210   211   212   213   >>   >|  



Top keywords:
instances
 

instance

 
invariable
 

absent

 

sequence

 

negative

 
antecedent
 

events

 
consequent
 
follow

supposable

 

accidental

 

cogency

 

simple

 

enumeration

 
condition
 

indispensable

 

effects

 

observed

 

connection


eliminate

 

consequents

 
antecedents
 

occasional

 
direct
 

causation

 
traceable
 

experience

 

requires

 
neglect

collect
 

examples

 

contribution

 

Inductive

 

agreement

 

strong

 

belief

 

phenome

 

numerous

 

respect


making

 

finding

 

considered

 
insist
 
present
 

moment

 

immediately

 

circumstance

 

Moreover

 
conditions