FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   350   351   352   353   354   355   356   357   358   359   360   361   362   363   364   365   366   367   368   369   370   371   372   373   374  
375   376   377   378   379   380   381   382   383   384   385   386   387   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399   >>   >|  
stinctions or differences. In scientific inquiry, differences are as crucial in the forming of generalizations as similarities. It is only possible to classify a given fact under a scientific generalization when the given fact is set off from other facts, when it is seen to be the result of certain special conditions. If a man infers from a single sample of grain as to the grade of wheat of the car as a whole, it is induction, and under certain circumstances, a _sound_ induction; other cases are resorted to simply for the sake of rendering that induction more guarded and correct. In the case of the various samples of grain, it is the fact that the samples are unlike, at least in the part of the carload from which they are taken, that is important. Were it not for this unlikeness, their likeness in quality would be of no avail in assisting inference.[1] [Footnote 1: Dewey: _How We Think_, pp. 89-90.] EXPERIMENTAL VARIATION OF CONDITIONS. In forming our generalizations from the observation of situations as they occur in Nature, we are at a disadvantage. If we observe cases just as we find them, there is much present that is irrelevant to our problem; much that is of genuine importance in its solution is hidden or obscure. In experimental investigation we are, in the words of Sir John Herschel, "active observers"; we deliberately invent crucial or test cases. That is, we deliberately arrange conditions so that every factor is definitely known and recognized. We then introduce into this set of completely known conditions one change, one new circumstance, and observe its effect. In Mill's phrase, we "take a phenomenon home with us," and watch its behavior. Mill states clearly the outstanding advantage of experimentation over observation: When we can produce a phenomenon artificially, we can take it, as it were, home with us, and observe it in the midst of circumstances with which in all other respects we are accurately acquainted. If we desire to know what are the effects of the cause _A_, and are able to produce _A_ by means at our disposal, we can generally determine at our own discretion ... the whole of the circumstances which shall be present along with it; and thus, knowing exactly the simultaneous state of everything else which is within the reach of _A's_ influence, we have only to observe what alteration is made in that state by the presence of _A_. For example, by the electric machine we can produce, i
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   350   351   352   353   354   355   356   357   358   359   360   361   362   363   364   365   366   367   368   369   370   371   372   373   374  
375   376   377   378   379   380   381   382   383   384   385   386   387   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399   >>   >|  



Top keywords:
observe
 

conditions

 
induction
 

circumstances

 

produce

 

differences

 
samples
 

present

 
deliberately
 
generalizations

forming

 

crucial

 

phenomenon

 

observation

 

scientific

 
introduce
 

machine

 

outstanding

 

behavior

 

invent


states

 

arrange

 
circumstance
 

recognized

 
completely
 

change

 
factor
 

phrase

 

effect

 
presence

determine
 

discretion

 

knowing

 

influence

 

simultaneous

 

generally

 

disposal

 

alteration

 

respects

 

artificially


experimentation

 

accurately

 

acquainted

 
electric
 
desire
 

effects

 

advantage

 

Nature

 

guarded

 
correct