FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   385   386   387   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399   400   401   402   403   404   405   406   407   408   409  
410   411   412   413   414   415   416   >>  
tent to indicate the truth roughly, and in outline.[1] [Footnote 1: Aristotle: _loc. cit._, pp. 3-4.] He points out repeatedly that situations are specific, that laws or generalization can only be tentatively made. Questions of practice and expediency no more admit of invariable rules than questions of health. But if this is true of general reasoning upon Ethics, still more true is it that scientific exactitude is impossible in reasoning upon particular ethical cases. They do not fall under any art or any law, but the agents themselves are always bound to pay regard to the circumstances of the moment, as much as in medicine or navigation.[1] [Footnote 1: Aristotle: _loc. cit._, p. 37.] Instead of framing absolute general rules, Aristotle points out those specific conditions which must be taken into account in any act that can, without quibbling, be called good or virtuous. It is possible to go too far, or not to go far enough, in respect of fear, courage, desire, anger, pity, and pleasure and pain generally, and the excess and the deficiency are alike wrong; but to experience these emotions at the right time, and on the right occasions and towards the right persons, and for the right causes and in the right manner is the mean or the supreme good, which is characteristic of virtue.[2] [Footnote 2: _Ibid_. p. 46.] Reflection thus unduly simplifies the moral problem by setting up general standards which are not adequate to the multiple variety of specific situations which constitute human experience. But in reasoning upon the conduct of life, there has been displayed, furthermore, by ethical writers an inveterate tendency to identify the processes of life with the process of reason. One may cite as a classic instance of this point of view the ethical theory of Jeremy Bentham and the Utilitarians. According to the Utilitarians human beings judged acts in terms of their utility, as measured in the amount of pleasure and pain produced by an action. The individual figured out the pleasures and pains that would be the consequences of his action. We shall in the next section examine this point of view in more detail; we are referring to it here simply as an illustration of intellectualizing of morals. Few individuals go through anything remotely resembling the "hedonic calculus" laid down by Bentham.[3] The individual is not a static being, mathematically considering the amount of pleasure and pain associat
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   385   386   387   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399   400   401   402   403   404   405   406   407   408   409  
410   411   412   413   414   415   416   >>  



Top keywords:

reasoning

 
ethical
 
general
 

pleasure

 

Footnote

 

specific

 

Aristotle

 

experience

 

amount

 

individual


action

 
points
 

situations

 
Utilitarians
 
Bentham
 

identify

 

processes

 

classic

 

reason

 

instance


process

 

problem

 

setting

 

standards

 

simplifies

 
Reflection
 

unduly

 

adequate

 

multiple

 
displayed

writers

 

inveterate

 

theory

 

variety

 
constitute
 

conduct

 

tendency

 
utility
 

individuals

 

morals


intellectualizing
 

referring

 

simply

 

illustration

 

remotely

 

resembling

 

mathematically

 

associat

 

static

 
hedonic