FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   26   27   28   29   30   31   32   33   34   35   36   37   38   39   40   41   42   43   44   45   46   >>  
igns of disease and the treatment that was appropriate. All were beautifully interdigitated in a logical fashion, and for any recommended therapy a good reason could be found. There was, however, a serious difficulty. If anyone were so bold as to ask, _But how do you know?_ only a rather lame answer would come forth. The exposition rested in large part on authority or else largely on reasoning from accepted premises--a "just" reasoning. And while much keen observation was duly recorded and a considerable mass of fact underlay the theoretical superstructure, the idea of empirical proof was not current. Riverius chopped logic vigorously and drew conclusions from unsupported assertions in a way that strikes us as reckless. For a body of knowledge to be a science, it must indicate a logical connection between first principles, which were "universal," and the particular case. The well-educated physician could always give a logical reason for what he did. The empiric, however, was one who carried out his remedies or procedures without being able to tell _why_. That is, he could not trace out the logical connection between first principles and the particular case. Galenism suffered especially from logical systematization, and the system of van Helmont, while far less orderly, also had its own basic principles on which all else depended. Boyle, however, practiced medicine on a thoroughly different basis. He did not depend on system or logic. In the words that Hunter used to Jenner over a hundred years later, other physicians would _think_ the answers to their problems. Boyle, however, preferred to _try the experiment_. He wanted _facts_. But this attitude, which sounds so modern, so praiseworthy and enlightened, had one serious flaw. What _was_ a fact? And how did you know? This important problem, so significant for the growth of scientific medicine, we can study quite readily in the works of Robert Boyle. The problem, in a sense, resolves around the notion of credulity. What shall we believe? Boyle makes some distinctions between what he has seen with his own eyes and what other people report to have seen. Thus, he mentions "a very experienced and sober gentleman, who is much talked of" who cured cancer of the female breast "by the outward application of an indolent powder, some of which he also gave me." But, he adds cautiously, he has not yet "had the opportunity to make trial of it."[52] Clearly, since he cannot mak
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   26   27   28   29   30   31   32   33   34   35   36   37   38   39   40   41   42   43   44   45   46   >>  



Top keywords:

logical

 

principles

 
reasoning
 

connection

 

problem

 

medicine

 

system

 

reason

 

enlightened

 

beautifully


praiseworthy
 
modern
 
attitude
 

sounds

 

important

 

readily

 
scientific
 

significant

 

growth

 

wanted


experiment
 

Jenner

 

hundred

 

Hunter

 

fashion

 

depend

 

problems

 

preferred

 

answers

 

interdigitated


physicians
 

Robert

 

cancer

 

female

 

breast

 

talked

 

experienced

 

gentleman

 

outward

 

application


cautiously
 

powder

 

indolent

 

mentions

 

notion

 
credulity
 

Clearly

 

resolves

 

people

 

report