FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   188   189   190   191   192   193   194   195   196   197   198   199   200   201   202   203   204   205   206   207   208   209   210   211   212  
213   214   215   216   217   218   219   220   221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   229   230   231   232   233   234   235   236   237   >>   >|  
rms are so varied, and the uses to which they are applied so unlike each other."[270] All these are homologous in structure--they are formed after an ideal archetype or model, but that model or type is variously modified to adapt the animal to the sphere of life in which it is destined to move, and the organ itself to the functions it has to perform, whether swimming, flying, walking, or burrowing, or that varied manipulation of which the human hand is capable. These varied modifications of the vertebrated type, for special purposes, are unmistakable examples of final causation. Whilst the silent members, the rudimental limbs instanced by Oken, Martins, and others--as fulfilling no purpose, and serving no end, exist in conformity to an ideal archetype on which the bony skeletons of all vertebrated animals are formed,[271] and which has never been departed from since time began. This type, or model, or plan, is, however, itself an evidence of _design_ as much as the plan of a house. For to what standard are we referring when we say that two limbs are morphologically the same? Is it not an _ideal_ plan, a _mental_ pattern, a metaphysical conception? Now an _ideal_ implies a mind which preconceived the idea, and in which alone it really exists. It is only as "an _order of Divine thought_" that the doctrine of animal homologies is at all intelligible; and Homology is, therefore, the science which traces the outward embodiment of a Divine Idea.[272] The principle of intentionality or final causation, then, is not in any sense invalidated by the discovery of "a unity of plan" sweeping through the entire universe. [Footnote 270: Carpenter's "Comparative Physiology," p. 37.] [Footnote 271: Agassiz, "Essay on Classification," p. 10.] [Footnote 272: Whewell's "History of Inductive Sciences," vol. i. p. 644; "The Reign of Law," p. 208; Agassiz, "Essay on Classification," pp. 9-11.] We conclude that we are justly entitled to regard "the principle of intentionality" as a primary and necessary law of thought, under which we can not avoid conceiving and describing the facts of the universe--_the special adaptation of means to ends necessarily implies mind_. Whenever and wherever we observe the adaptation of an organism to the fulfillment of a special end, we can not avoid conceiving of that _end_ as foreseen and premeditated, the _means_ as selected and adjusted with a view to that end, and creative energy put forth to secure
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   188   189   190   191   192   193   194   195   196   197   198   199   200   201   202   203   204   205   206   207   208   209   210   211   212  
213   214   215   216   217   218   219   220   221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   229   230   231   232   233   234   235   236   237   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

varied

 

Footnote

 

special

 

vertebrated

 

principle

 

intentionality

 

conceiving

 

universe

 
Classification
 

causation


implies
 

formed

 

thought

 
Divine
 

animal

 
archetype
 
Agassiz
 

adaptation

 

embodiment

 

Physiology


Comparative

 

homologies

 
doctrine
 

intelligible

 
sweeping
 

science

 

traces

 

discovery

 
outward
 

Homology


Carpenter

 

entire

 

invalidated

 

observe

 

organism

 

fulfillment

 

Whenever

 

necessarily

 
describing
 
foreseen

premeditated

 

energy

 

secure

 

creative

 

selected

 

adjusted

 

Sciences

 

Whewell

 

History

 

Inductive