FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   25   26   27   28   29   30   31   32   33   34   35   36   37   38   39   40   41   42   43   44   45   46   47   48   49  
50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73   74   >>   >|  
ur senses and what is conceived of in the mind, is, as though unconsciously, taken for granted. Thus while he contends for a practical theism, the very basis of his interest still rests in the conviction of a Being external to us and existing independent of our thought. [Footnote 5: _The Critique of Practical Reason_ (tr. T.K. Abbott), p. 260.] [Footnote 6: _The Critique of Pure Reason_, p. 702.] But his intention of making right conduct the essence of religion is typical of the limits of humanistic interests and perceptions. In making his division of reason into the theoretical and the practical, it is to the latter realm that he assigns morality and religion. Clearly this is genuine rationalism. I am not forgetting Kant's great religious contribution. He was the son of devout German pietists and saturated in the literature of the Old Testament. It is to Amos, who may justly be called his spiritual father, that he owes the moral absoluteness of his categorical imperative, the reading of history as a moral order. He was following Amos when he took God out of the physical and put Him into the moral sphere and interpreted Him in the terms of purpose. But the doctrine of _The Critique of Practical Reason_ is intended to negate those transcendent elements generally believed to be the distinctive portions of religion. God is not known to us as an objective being, an entity without ourselves. He is an idea, a belief, which gives meaning to our ethical life, a subjective necessity. He is a postulate of the moral will. To quote Professor McGiffert again: "We do not get God from the universe, we give Him to the universe. We read significance and moral purpose into it. We assume God, not to account for the world, but for the subjective need of realizing our highest good.... Religion becomes a creative act of the moral will just as knowledge is a creative act of the understanding."[7] Thus there are no ultimate values; at least we can know nothing of them; we have nothing to look to which is objective and changeless. The absolutism of the Categorical Imperative is a subjective one, bounded by ourselves, formed of our substance. Religion is not discovered, but self-created, a sort of sublime expediency. It can carry, then, no confident assertion as to the meaning and destiny of the universe as a whole. [Footnote 7: _H.T.R._, vol. I, no. 1, p. 18.] Here, then, the nature of morality, the inspiration for character, the so
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   25   26   27   28   29   30   31   32   33   34   35   36   37   38   39   40   41   42   43   44   45   46   47   48   49  
50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73   74   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

subjective

 

Footnote

 

universe

 

religion

 

Reason

 

Critique

 

making

 

morality

 

objective

 
purpose

Religion
 

meaning

 

practical

 
Practical
 

creative

 

account

 
distinctive
 

portions

 
assume
 

significance


postulate
 

necessity

 

belief

 

ethical

 

entity

 

McGiffert

 

Professor

 

ultimate

 

expediency

 

confident


assertion

 

sublime

 

substance

 
discovered
 

created

 

destiny

 

nature

 
inspiration
 

character

 
formed

believed
 
values
 

understanding

 

knowledge

 

highest

 

Categorical

 

Imperative

 

bounded

 
absolutism
 

changeless