FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   355   356   357   358   359   360   361   362   363   364   365   366   367   368   369   370   371   372   373   374   375   376   377   378   379  
380   381   382   383   384   385   386   387   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399   400   401   402   403   404   >>   >|  
from a state of captivity in war; whence slaves are called _mancipia, quasi manu capti_. The conqueror, say the civilians, had a right to the life of his captive; and, having spared that, has a right to deal with him as he pleases. But it is an untrue position, when taken generally, that, by the law of nature or nations, a man may kill his enemy: he has only a right to kill him, in particular cases; in cases of absolute necessity, for self-defence; and it is plain this absolute necessity did not subsist, since the victor did not actually kill him, but made him prisoner. War is itself justifiable only on principles of self-preservation; and therefore it gives no other right over prisoners, but merely to disable them from doing harm to us, by confining their persons: much less can it give a right to kill, torture, abuse, plunder, or even to enslave, an enemy, when the war is over. Since therefore the right of _making_ slaves by captivity, depends on a supposed right of slaughter, that foundation failing, the consequence drawn from it must fail likewise. But, secondly, it is said that slavery may begin "_jure civili_;" when one man sells himself to another. This, if only meant of contracts to serve or work for another, is very just: but when applied to strict slavery, in the sense of the laws of old Rome or modern Barbary, is also impossible. Every sale implies a price, a _quid pro quo_, an equivalent given to the seller in lieu of what he transfers to the buyer: but what equivalent can be given for life, and liberty, both of which (in absolute slavery) are held to be in the master's disposal? His property also, the very price he seems to receive, devolves _ipso facto_ to his master, the instant he becomes his slave. In this case therefore the buyer gives nothing, and the seller receives nothing: of what validity then can a sale be, which destroys the very principles upon which all sales are founded? Lastly, we are told, that besides these two ways by which slaves "_fiunt_," or are acquired, they may also be hereditary: "_servi nascuntur_;" the children of acquired slaves are, _jure naturae_, by a negative kind of birthright, slaves also. But this being built on the two former rights must fall together with them. If neither captivity, nor the sale of oneself, can by the law of nature and reason, reduce the parent to slavery, much less can it reduce the offspring. [Footnote a: pag. 123.] [Footnote b: _Servi aut fiunt,
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   355   356   357   358   359   360   361   362   363   364   365   366   367   368   369   370   371   372   373   374   375   376   377   378   379  
380   381   382   383   384   385   386   387   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399   400   401   402   403   404   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

slaves

 

slavery

 
absolute
 

captivity

 

master

 
necessity
 
principles
 
acquired
 

equivalent

 

reduce


Footnote
 

seller

 

nature

 
receive
 
Barbary
 
devolves
 
instant
 

implies

 

impossible

 
disposal

transfers

 

liberty

 

property

 

hereditary

 

rights

 
birthright
 

oneself

 

reason

 

parent

 

offspring


negative

 

founded

 
Lastly
 

validity

 

destroys

 

nascuntur

 

children

 
naturae
 

modern

 

receives


consequence

 

subsist

 

victor

 

defence

 

generally

 
nations
 
prisoner
 

prisoners

 

disable

 

preservation