FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   27   28   29   30   31   32   33   34   35   36   37   38   39   40   41   42   43   44   45   46   47   48   49   50   51  
52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73   74   75   76   >>   >|  
eign is unavoidable, it is well to remember that the shift of opinion is, in our own time, more and more in the direction of Locke's attitude. That omnicompetence of Parliament which Bentham and Austin crystallized into the retort to Locke admits, in later hands, of exactly the amelioration he had in mind; and its ethical inadequacy becomes the more obvious the more closely it is studied.[5] [Footnote 5: Cf. my _Problem of Sovereignty_, Chap. I.] The internal limitation Locke suggested is of more doubtful value. Government, he says, in substance, is a trustee and trustees abuse their power; let us therefore divide it as to parts and persons that the temptation to usurp may be diminished. There is a long history to this doctrine in its more obvious form, and it is a lamentable history. It tied men down to a tyrannous classification which had no root in the material it was supposed to distinguish. Montesquieu took it for the root of liberty; Blackstone, who should have known better, repeated the pious phrases of the Frenchman; and they went in company to America to persuade Madison and the Supreme Court of the United States that only the separation of powers can prevent the approach of tyranny. The facts do not bear out such assumption. The division of powers means in the event not less than their confusion. None can differentiate between the judge's declaration of law and his making of it.[6] Every government department is compelled to legislate, and, often enough, to undertake judicial functions. The American history of the separation of powers has most largely been an attempt to bridge them; and all that has been gained is to drive the best talent, save on rare occasion, from its public life. In France the separation of powers meant, until recent times, the excessive subordination of the judiciary to the cabinet. Nor must we forget, as Locke should have remembered, the plain lesson of the Cromwellian constitutional experiments. That the dispersion of power is one of the great needs of the modern State at no point justifies the rigid categories into which Locke sought its division.[7] [Footnote 6: Cf. Mr. Justice Holmes' remarks in _Jensen_ v. _Southern Pacific_, 244 U.S. 221.] [Footnote 7: Cf. my _Authority in the Modern State_, pp. 70 f.] Nor must we belittle the criticism, in its clearest form the work of Fitz James Stephen,[8] that has been levelled at Locke's theory of toleration. For the larger part of th
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   27   28   29   30   31   32   33   34   35   36   37   38   39   40   41   42   43   44   45   46   47   48   49   50   51  
52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73   74   75   76   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

powers

 

history

 

Footnote

 

separation

 
obvious
 

division

 

differentiate

 

talent

 

France

 

occasion


public

 

legislate

 

undertake

 
judicial
 
making
 
government
 

department

 

compelled

 

functions

 

attempt


bridge

 

declaration

 

American

 
recent
 

largely

 

gained

 
dispersion
 
Modern
 

belittle

 
Authority

Pacific
 

Southern

 
criticism
 

clearest

 
toleration
 

larger

 

theory

 
levelled
 

Stephen

 

Jensen


Cromwellian

 
lesson
 

constitutional

 

experiments

 
confusion
 

remembered

 

subordination

 

excessive

 
judiciary
 

cabinet