FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   288   289   290   291   292   293   294   295   296   297   298   299   300   301   302   303   304   305   306   307   308   309   310   311   312  
313   314   315   316   317   318   319   320   321   322   323   324   325   326   327   328   329   330   331   332   333   334   335   336   337   >>   >|  
e latter, moreover, in anticipation of the Critique of Reason, pointing very definitely to the distinction between content and form as the salient point in the theory of knowledge. [Footnote 1: Benno Erdmann, _M. Knutzen und seine Zeit_, 1876.] [Footnote 2: Th. W. Danzel, _Gottsched und seine Zeit_, 1848.] [Footnote 3: Lambert: _Cosmological Letters_, 1761; _New Organon_, 1764; _Groundwork of Architectonics_, 1771. Bernoulli edited some of Lambert's papers and his correspondence.] Among the opponents of the Wolffian philosophy, all of whom favor eclecticism, A. Ruediger[1] and Chr. Aug. Crusius,[2] who was influenced by Ruediger, and, like him, a professor at Leipsic, are the most important. Ruediger divides philosophy according to its objects, "wisdom, justice, prudence," into three parts--the science of nature (which must avoid one-sided mechanical views, and employ ether, air, and spirit as principles of explanation); the science of duty (which, as metaphysics, treats of duties toward God, as natural law, of duties to our neighbor, and deduces both from the primary duty of obedience to the will of God); and the science of the good (in which Ruediger follows the treatise of the Spaniard, Gracian, on practical wisdom). Crusius agrees with Ruediger that mathematics is the science of the possible, and philosophy the science of the actual, and that the latter, instead of imitating to its own disadvantage the deductive-analytical method of geometry, must, with the aid of experience and with attention to the probability of its conclusions, rise to the highest principles synthetically. Besides its deduction the determinism of the Wolffian philosophy gave offense, for it was believed to endanger morals, justice, and religion. The will, the special fundamental power of the soul (consisting of the impulses to perfection, love, and knowledge), is far from being determined by ideas; it is rather they which depend on the will. The application of the principle of sufficient reason, which is wrongly held to admit of no exception, must be restricted in favor of freedom. For the rest, we may note concerning Crusius that he derives the principle of sufficient reason (everything which is now, and before was not, has a cause) and the principle of contingency from the principles of contradiction, inseparability, and incompatibility, and these latter from the principle of conceivability; that he rejects the ontological argument, and
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   288   289   290   291   292   293   294   295   296   297   298   299   300   301   302   303   304   305   306   307   308   309   310   311   312  
313   314   315   316   317   318   319   320   321   322   323   324   325   326   327   328   329   330   331   332   333   334   335   336   337   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

science

 
Ruediger
 
philosophy
 

principle

 
Crusius
 
Footnote
 

principles

 

sufficient

 

Wolffian

 

reason


justice

 

duties

 
Lambert
 

wisdom

 
knowledge
 

synthetically

 

Besides

 
highest
 

conclusions

 

attention


probability

 

deduction

 

offense

 

endanger

 

morals

 
religion
 

believed

 

conceivability

 
determinism
 

mathematics


argument

 

actual

 

anticipation

 

Gracian

 
practical
 

agrees

 

imitating

 

analytical

 

method

 
geometry

rejects
 
deductive
 

ontological

 

disadvantage

 

experience

 

fundamental

 

restricted

 

freedom

 
exception
 

derives