FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   230   231   232   233   234   235   236   237   238   239   240   241   242   243   244   245   246   247   248   249   250   251   252   253   254  
255   256   257   258   259   260   261   262   263   264   265   266   267   268   269   270   271   272   273   274   275   276   277   278   279   >>   >|  
image of this property, but merely a sign for something in no wise resembling itself. This is the standpoint of the founder[1] of the Scottish School, Thomas Reid (1710-96, professor in Aberdeen and Glasgow; _An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense_, 1764; _Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man_, 1785, _Essays on the Active Powers_, 1788, together under the title, _Essays on the Powers of the Human Mind. Collected Works_, 1804, and often since, especially the edition by Hamilton, with valuable notes and dissertations, 7th ed., 2 vols., 1872). We may recognize in it a revival of the common notions of Herbert, as well as a transfer of the innate faculty of judgment inculcated by the ethical and aesthetic writers from the practical to the theoretical field; the "common sense" of Reid is an original sense for truth, as the "taste" of Shaftesbury and Hutcheson was a natural sense for the good and the beautiful. Like Jacobi at a later period, Reid points out that mediate, reasoned knowledge presupposes a knowledge which is immediate, and all inference and demonstration, fixed, undemonstrable, immediately certain fundamental truths. The fundamental judgments or principles of common sense, which are true for us, even if [possibly] not true in themselves, are discoverable by observation (empirical rationalism). In the enumeration of them two dangers are to be avoided: we must neither raise contingent principles to the position of axioms, nor, from an exaggerated endeavor after unity, underestimate the number of these self-evident principles. Reid himself is always more sparing with them than his disciples. He distinguishes two classes: first principles of necessary truth, and first principles of contingent truth or truth of fact. As first principles of necessary truth he cites, besides the axioms of logic and mathematics, grammatical, aesthetic, moral, and metaphysical principles (among the last belong the principles: "That the qualities which we perceive by our senses must have a subject, which we call body, and that the thoughts we are conscious of must have a subject, which we call mind"; "that whatever begins to exist, must have a cause which produced it"). He lays down twelve principles as the basis of our knowledge of matters of fact, in which his reference to the doubt of Berkeley and Hume is evident. The most important of these are: "The existence of everything of which I am conscious"; "that
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   230   231   232   233   234   235   236   237   238   239   240   241   242   243   244   245   246   247   248   249   250   251   252   253   254  
255   256   257   258   259   260   261   262   263   264   265   266   267   268   269   270   271   272   273   274   275   276   277   278   279   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

principles

 

common

 

Powers

 

Essays

 
knowledge
 

subject

 

aesthetic

 

contingent

 
fundamental
 

axioms


evident
 
conscious
 

dangers

 

avoided

 

position

 

reference

 

endeavor

 

Berkeley

 

exaggerated

 

important


property
 

possibly

 

rationalism

 

enumeration

 

empirical

 

existence

 
discoverable
 
observation
 

underestimate

 
grammatical

mathematics

 

metaphysical

 
senses
 

thoughts

 

perceive

 
qualities
 
belong
 

begins

 

matters

 

twelve


sparing

 

classes

 

produced

 
distinguishes
 

disciples

 
number
 

Collected

 

edition

 

Hamilton

 
valuable